Chapter 16 The Theistic Bottom Line Part A
The three large principles summed up
in the previous chapter are enough. With them established, we have enough to
conclude that there is a higher power or consciousness in the material universe
in which we live. Or rather, as was promised in the introduction, we have
enough to conclude that belief in God is a rational choice for a thinking,
informed, modern human being to make.
And that is the whole point. Belief
in God is a choice. It is simply a more rational choice than its alternatives.
It is also worth re-iterating three other points here: first, we must have a
moral program in our heads to function at all; second, the one we've inherited
from the past is dangerously out-of-date; and third, whatever new one we
devise, it will have to be turned from a cerebral code into a personal one. A
moral code must be felt and lived as personal or else it isn't really a moral
code at all.
This
final chapter gives the more informal explanation and interpretation of the
pieces that have been assembled so far, and adds some other, better known
pieces whose significance in this discussion will now be explained as we go.
Along the way, it also tries to answer some of the most likely reactions to
this book. My promise was that at the end of this book, we would be able to
assemble a strong case for theism, i.e. belief in God. We're almost there. We
shall begin this last chapter by revisiting, in a more personal way, a vexing
problem in Philosophy mentioned in an earlier chapter, a problem that is three
hundred years old. The solution to this vexing problem drives home our first
main point on the final stretch of the thinking process that leads to theism.
photo
representing popular image of a scientist
Many scientists claim that their branch of human knowledge,
unlike all of the ones that came before the rise of Science, does not have any
basic assumptions at its foundation and that it is instead built from the
ground up on merely observing reality, hypothesizing, designing and doing research,
checking results against one's hypothesis, and then doing more hypothesizing,
research, etc. Under this view, Science has no need of unprovable foundational
assumptions in the way that, say, Philosophy or Euclidean Geometry do. Science
is founded only on hard fact, they claim. But in this claim, as has been
pointed out by thinkers like Nicholas Maxwell, those scientists are wrong. (1.)
Over
the last four centuries, the scientific way of thinking, Bacon’s “new
instrument”, has made possible the amazing progress in human knowledge and
technology that today we associate with Science. But in the meantime, at least
for philosophers, it has come in for some tougher analysis.
cover of early
copy of "Novum Organum"
The heart of the matter, then, is the inductive method that is
normally associated with Science. The way in which scientists can come upon a
phenomenon that they cannot explain with any of the models that they currently
have, then devise a new theory that tries to explain the phenomenon, then test
the theory by doing experiments in the material world, then keep going back and
forth from theory to experiment, adjusting and refining – this is the way of
gaining knowledge that is called the "scientific method". It has led
us to so many powerful new insights and technologies. It really was an amazing
breakthrough when Francis Bacon – whether we credit him with originating it or
merely expressing what many in his era were already thinking – saw and
explained what he called his “new instrument” (Novum Organum). We owe him more
than more than all could pay.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.