The
conclusion to be drawn from all this is that the Enlightenment worldview, with
the moral code that attends it, is no longer an adequate code for us to live
by. It is ready for another update. In the midst of its successes, it has also
produced huge problems such as the oppression of women and minorities, social
inequities, technology-driven wars, colonialism, the proliferation of nuclear
weapons, and pollution levels that will soon destroy the earth’s ecosystem if
they’re allowed to go on unchecked. Some of the problems look as if they are out
of control, and even more frightening, the Enlightenment worldview appears to
have run out of ideas for ways to solve them.
The
crucial point of this long discussion of the rise of the West is that world
views give rise to value systems and value systems give rise to morés. The morés
then cluster to form a culture or way of life that has a survival index in the
real world. Furthermore, some morés and habits of living, when they come to be believed
and practiced by the majority of a society’s citizens, increase that society’s
survival odds more than others do. By our morés and our patterns of behaviour,
we interface with physical reality. Then, if the values are tuned to our
current reality, we thrive.
But
I stress again that the world views, values, morés, and behaviour patterns that
we humans live by are not all, as cultural relativism claims, of equal value
and are not part of our way of life because of random inclinations flitting
through our brains. This book offers a more rigorous model for understanding these
ideas.
Of
course, other civilizations have also had eras during which they were in
ascendancy. In fact, many economic and political signs today indicate that the
dominance of the West may be ending. The new worldview science is offering and
the values and morés it fosters are so different from the ones out of which the
successes of the West grew that cultures of the West, as they try to adjust,
sometimes seem to be verging on self-destruction. We must strive to insure that
the obsolete parts of the Western worldview will not be replaced by others that
simply lead to new forms of injustice, but that instead humanity will finally
enter a period of peaceful integration of all human cultures. With the problems
and hazards that we have before us now, there doesn’t seem to be much hope for
our species if we can’t do this work.
Discussing
and interpreting the moral implications of the new worldview offered by the new
physics will be the business of my next two chapters. I will present a moral
code and an argument for it that is not as all-encompassing as Hegel’s but is more
useful. The theory of morality presented in the remainder of this book offers
some firmer measures by which to judge our actions.
Karl Popper
However,
this new theory will not satisfy the demands of the most exacting philosophers,
such as, for example, Karl Popper and his disciples.4 Popper loved
the physical sciences and considered them to be models of what science should
be, but he found biology disappointing because he felt its foundational
theories (notably the theory of evolution) could not be tested in neat, clear
ways to see whether they could be falsified. He wrote off the social sciences
pretty much completely.
Popper
argued that only theories that can be tested in ways that risk their being falsified
deserve to be called science. For example, he was deeply impressed by the theory
of relativity, because it could be tested definitively. If it had failed to
predict Eddington’s observations of the stars visible during a full solar
eclipse, the theory would have been viewed as a failure. But it succeeded
brilliantly, and Einstein’s international reputation soared.
Biology
is not that neat. The theory of evolution can be tested only in ways that, if
successful, may make it seem more likely to be true. In his early work, Popper
did not even want to call biology a science. But gradually, over years, he came
to concede that some theories could make probabilistic, Bayesian kinds of
predictions rather than neat, causally linked ones and still be rigorous enough
to be properly called scientific. The psychological theories of Adler and the
historical ones of Marx weren’t that useful, but Popper came to see that the theory
of evolution was.5
We
accept now that the history of life does not proceed by
cause-and-effect steps as they are pictured under the Enlightenment world view.
Instead, life proceeds forward through time like a river, with many branches
and tributaries connecting to the main channel. The difference is that life
flows uphill. It flows against the gradient of entropy, opportunistically
searching for new habitats in which some new species or new ways of life may
take root, adapt, and flourish. This is a better metaphor for describing how
life moves across time.
Under
this model, the life flow keep bifurcating. Some forks take detours and some are
blocked completely and die out. Whether a given branch will surface further on
in the natural history of the world is dependent on many odds-governed factors
such as changing climates and mutation rates of other species (especially those
that are its food, its competition, and its predators). But the entire system
keeps expanding relentlessly, as is shown by the way the amount of biomass on our
planet has been increasing since life began here about three billion years ago.
While
the model of human cultural evolution presented in the rest of this book will
not satisfy Popper’s most rigorous early demands, it will do what we need it to
do. It will give us categories and guidelines that will lead us toward better
odds of surviving over the long term.
Notes
1.
Matthew Allen Fox, The Accessible Hegel
(Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, 2005).
2.
Edith Hamilton, Mythology: Timeless Tales
of Gods and Heroes (New York, NY: Warner Books, 1999), pp. 16–19.
3. Edward Gibbon, History of
the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. 1 (1776; Project Gutenberg).
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/731/731-h/731-h.html.
4.
Karl Popper, “Science: Conjectures and Refutations,” in Martin Curd and J.A.
Cover, Philosophy of Science: The Central
Issues (New York, NY: W.W. Norton and Co., 1998).
5. Mark
Isaak, ed., Index to Creationist Claims, The
Talk Origins Archive, 2005. http://www.talkorigins.org/indexcc/CA/CA211_1.html.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.