Thus
in Western history, the next important worldview is the Roman one. Operating
under it, people became even more practical, more focused on physical effectiveness
and power, and less interested in, or even aware of, ideas for their own sake. Among
many of the early Romans, this feeling expressed itself in a hatred of all
things Greek; the truth was that, though they did not like to admit it, the early
Romans borrowed heavily from the Greeks, especially in theoretical knowledge.
In
their heyday, the Romans no longer feared the gods in the way the ancient
Greeks and the Romans’ own ancestors once had. As the Republic faded and the Empire
took over, the Romans turned so far from earlier thinking that they lost much
of the Greek, especially the Athenian, capacity for abstract things—wonder,
idealism, pure geometry, pure philosophical speculation, and flights of
imagination and of their own sense of duty to one’s nation. The Romans built
their state on Athenian-style, democratic principles, values, and behaviours,
but like the Spartans, they loved results and power, not speculation.
Pont
du Gard: Roman aqueduct in present-day France (credit: Wikimedia Commons)
It is tempting to see in the Romans’ culture a synthesis of the
ways of the Athenians and those of the Spartans. This is an example of Hegel’s dialectic:
one way of thinking, along with the human groups that gather around it, forms
and grows, and then an opposite way of thinking rises up like a kind of cosmic
response to the first way. The two struggle, interact, and finally meld into a
true synthesis, which is not like a compromise because it is a new, coherent,
unified way with a life of its own.
The people born into the new way are not aware they are using some
elements from one philosophy and some from another. The new way is simply their
way, and ideas that are added to the new system make it feel like a seamless
whole. Thesis, antithesis, then synthesis, over and over, with the system spiralling
upward to greater and greater consciousness. This is Hegel’s model of human
social evolution.
It is tempting. It is a
fairly simple model, and with a little stretching it can be made to seem to fit
in era after era and country after country when we study human history. But it
is simply too simple. The Roman ways of thinking of life did contain some ideals
similar to those of both the Athenians and the Spartans, but we know there was
too much else going on in the thinking and living style of the Romans for Hegel’s
model to be seen as satisfactory today. The Romans also came into power in the ancient world by a culture that was their own, evolved over generations of farmers who banded together to protect their farms and their families and built a city as a central fortress that would facilitate their realizing this goal. Human societies are subtler than Hegel's model.
What makes more sense is to examine each historical society‘s worldview,
values, morés, and behaviour patterns and observe how they coordinated to
produce a whole culture and way of life that met the citizens’ survival needs
at the time. Under that humbler view, we can learn much more about how human
societies really work.
The model of human cultural evolution presented in this book doesn’t
attempt to be as all-encompassing as Hegel’s thesis-antithesis-synthesis model
because the process of human cultural evolution doesn’t fit Hegel’s model.
Rather, the process of human cultural evolution is more closely analogous to
the process of evolution in the rest of nature—by genetic variation and natural
selection and accident and disaster.
Life didn’t move forward through time and proliferate into its
many forms by the mechanism that Hegel describes. In the past, conditions like
tsunamis, earthquakes, floods, droughts, volcanic eruptions, and even
collisions with giant meteors suddenly closed down, or opened up, reams of opportunities.
Then, usually, life forms moved in opportunistically. Life spreads across time
and space not like a chain or road, but like a bush branching and bifurcating from
that primal trunk started from a few cells eons ago.
The model of human cultural evolution presented in this book can’t
match Hegel’s dialectic for cognitive attractiveness. Hegel’s model seems so
neat and complete. But life isn’t that neat, and our models of human culture
must be placed in the realm of the living. The model explored here can do what
we need it to do. It can give us enough insights into how human cultures work,
and what right and wrong are, for us to be able to build a rational moral code. One
that maximizes our odds of survival. And that is all we need.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.