Chapter 2 – The Moral Emptiness
Of Science
William Butler Yeats (credit: Wikimedia Commons)
Things fall apart; the
centre cannot hold;
Mere anarchy is loosed
upon the world,
The blood-dimmed tide is
loosed, and everywhere
The ceremony of innocence
is drowned;
The best lack all
conviction, while the worst
Are full of passionate
intensity.
—from “The Second Coming”
by W.B. Yeats, 1919
When our idea of God
began to erode, so did our ideas of right and wrong, and when those ideas began
to erode, we became the society that Yeats described in his great poem “The
Second Coming”. We live in a time in which some of the most immoral of citizens
are filled with “passionate intensity”: fraudsters claim they are daring entrepreneurs;
Mafia thugs claim that they are just soldiers in one more kind of war;
warmonger generals tout their own indispensability. In short, these people see
themselves as moral, even heroic, beings.
In the meantime, some of
what should be society’s most moral citizens “lack all conviction.” For
example, it would seem logical that people looking for moral direction in the
Science-driven countries of the West would turn to their gurus, i.e.
scientists. Especially those who study human societies and the moral beliefs they
run by. In the West, these experts are our anthropologists and sociologists.
Trained to make astute, Science-based judgments about human societies and
their “ways of life”, social scientists should be our most morally gifted
citizens.
But social scientists in
the West have no moral directions to offer their fellow citizens. In their
writings, they flatly deny that moral values refer to anything real at all. American
anthropologist Ruth Benedict put it succinctly: “Morality differs in every
society and is a convenient term for socially approved habits.”1 Thus,
as moral guides, Science and scientists – social scientists, in particular –
appear to be pretty close to useless.
How can this be? How can
highly intelligent people who set as their life purpose a full comprehension of
why humans in groups behave in the ways that they do – and who engage in years
of study and research intended to bring them to that goal – how can they then
tell us that the moral codes all people learn as children, and consult to guide
their behavior, their choices, and actions every day, are all hollow, devoid of
content? This picture defies sense. If social scientists aren’t working to
understand why groups of humans act as they do, what are they doing? If
humans’ stated moral codes are unrelated to their actions, even though they say
those codes are what guide their actions, then why do all those people – observed
and observers – talk about their moral sentiments at all? Is it all verbal
“grooming behavior” that does nothing but fill idle time?
But in response to
questions about what moral codes are, and how they relate to humans’ real
actions, most social scientists, as noted above, say their studies have led
them to conclude that moral codes have no grounding in the real world. Moral
claims are just expressions of tastes, like a preference for one brand of
perfume or flavor of ice cream over its competitors. Statements about “right”
and “wrong” are just ways of venting emotion. “Right” and “wrong” are empty
concepts, unrelated to any empirical facts. These experts then challenge their opponents
to prove otherwise.
Many even go over to the
offence and ask what it is that all Science is seeking. Are scientists seeking
truth about reality? That, by pure Logic, is unattainable. But, if not truth,
sociologists ask, then what is Science seeking? The answers to these questions
are parts of a fight going on in universities worldwide right now.
Thomas Kuhn’s The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions is arguably the most influential work on
this topic. In it, he casts a dark shadow over Science’s view of itself.
He argues that in reality all branches of Science move forward via processes that are not rational. The
scientific method is driven by intuition, not logic. Science does not progress
by a steady march of improving knowledge; it moves from less useful pictures of
reality to more useful ones by unpredictable leaps that he calls paradigm
shifts.
A paradigm shift occurs in
a branch of Science when many individuals in that branch, separately, each have
a moment of insight and then experience a leap of understanding so profound that
it makes them literally see reality in a new way. But they cannot tell you
after their cognitive leap has occurred how it came to pass, and they then came
to grasp this new picture of the world.
Scientists who grasp a
paradigm shift do indeed come to “see” the world in a totally new way because
their minds then have been reprogrammed to see different patterns in the details
around them. That’s how profoundly the new model, once they learn it, affects
them. Each scientist who “gets it” experiences a kind of “conversion” that
steers her/him into a community of fellow believers.
In all branches of
Science, Kuhn claims, old ways of thinking are dropped, and new models become
accepted ones via this process that appears to be driven at least as much by non-rational
mental processes as by rational steps like theorize, test, and repeat.
Clearly, the modes of thinking that enable Science to evolve run deeper than
reasoning and evidence can explain. Kuhn gives many examples from the History
of Science to support his case. His work has evoked many responses, pro and con,
but there is no doubt that he has shone a troubling light on the reliability of
all of Science.2 In short, Science is not done scientifically.
In the meantime, counterattacks
aimed back at the social sciences are made by critics like philosopher John
Searle. He admires the physical sciences because, he claims, they can be logically
rigorous. Physical sciences describe their theories and the studies designed to
test them using unambiguous terms. (One calorie heats one gram of water one
Celsius degree.) But the social sciences use models that are too vague to
support rigorous reasoning. (In Anthropology, what makes a “big man”?) Thus, conclusions
reached in social science are not reliable.3 (Critics of social
science are well countered in Harold Kincaid’s Philosophical Foundations of
the Social Sciences.4)
Clash of cultures: skulls of buffalo shot
by U.S. government hunters, 1880’s
(credit: Wikimedia
Commons)
In response to the
criticisms of the “unscientificness” of their discipline, some social
scientists have tried hard to be more rigorous in their work. However, many
have admitted Searle is at least partly right. For example, studies done in Anthropology
are usually difficult to replicate for a whole array of reasons. Thus, careful
checking and re-testing theories in social science is not possible.
Here let’s recall that,
in order to qualify as “scientific”, a model or theory must be testable in the
real world, and the tests must be replicable. If the tests can’t be replicated,
the theory is not Science. Tell me how you test your theory. Then, I can check
it by doing those tests myself. Easy to do in Physics and Chemistry where
materials and pieces of apparatus are standardized. All but impossible in Sociology
and Anthropology.
Many factors other than its
vague terms make social science’s studies hard to replicate.
First, background
conditions of studies in social science often can’t be reset. Socially relevant
facts keep changing. For example, how could a tribe return to living as fishers
if the species they once caught off their coasts are gone?
In social science, we also
accept implicitly that, even when conditions in the world can be “reset”, that no
custom should ever be forced on a tribe. For example, trying to get a tribe to
go back to living naked once they have chosen to wear clothes would be
unethical. Tribes in the Amazon, once they join a society where clothes are
worn, don’t want to live naked anymore. Cultural anthropologists would not try
to make these people go back to living naked, as they had been living just a
few years before. The anthropologists’ own moral code tells them that trying to
“guide” changes in a tribe’s way of life to aid research – or for any other
purpose – is wrong. Social scientists are ethically bound to observe societies
as they live, but never to interfere in their changes.
In addition, a
researcher’s own biases influence what she looks for and how she sees it. These
biases are impossible to avoid, no matter how carefully the studies are
designed. People of the Amazon see trails of peccary or cayman in
crushed grasses. But Western anthropologists see details they have been
programmed to notice (e.g. flowers, insects). An anthropologist living with an
Amazon tribe needs years of training before she can learn to track peccaries.
Finally, a social
scientist’s watching a tribe of people also changes what is being watched,
namely the morés of those people. For example, an anthropologist in the field usually
can’t work without shoes. Often in only weeks, the folk she’s living with and
studying, if they have been living barefoot, start to want shoes.
For all of these reasons
then, social scientists admit they often must settle for what is really a
single occurrence of the social phenomenon they wish to study. One that can’t
be replicated. But no generalizations can be drawn from a single, unrepeatable
instance of anything. That’s a direct contradiction of what the word “generalize”
means.
These difficulties with social
science research put us in a logical quandary.
Societies vary widely in
their beliefs and morés, and those morés keep changing even while
scientists are studying them. There are many human tribes to study, and each contains
many customs that are changing all the time. Social scientists will never adequately
document all the societies of the world as they are now.
Thus, we’ll never arrive
at any useful conclusions in social science unless we can first propose larger,
more generic theories of how human societies work.
In fact, social
scientists see that kind of plan as being immoral from its outset because it
amounts to Europeans imposing their ways on other cultures. In the meantime, critics
of social science say such a grand theory can’t be formulated. They insist
absolutely that social science is too vague, from its terms on up, to ever
enable its practitioners to create a general theory of how societies work.
If such a theory ever were
articulated, it would give direction and focus to all social science work. Under
it, social scientists could propose and test specific hypotheses. But until
social science has a comprehensive theory to guide its research, it will remain
what Ernest Rutherford dismissively called “stamp collecting”: people recording
data but making no attempt to explain them.
Cooperation of cultures:
soldiers of the 8 nations alliance during
the Boxer Rebellion in China, 1900
(credit: Wikimedia Commons)
At this point, some social
scientists’ respond to their critics with further, more aggressive counterattacks
of their own. They argue that no science, not Physics itself, is “objective”.
Culturally-slanted biases shape all human thinking – even the thinking of
physicists. For example, over a century ago Western physicists postulated, and went
looking for, what they called “atoms”, because early in Western history, a
philosopher named “Democritus” had postulated the idea of that the world is
made of atoms. Once instruments capable of reaching into very tiny levels of
matter became available, Westerners had already available the concept that
enabled them to imagine and set up experiments at that level. It had been
planted there during the educations they acquired in their cultures. But Democritus
did not derive the idea of the atom from observations of any “atoms”. The idea
was purely a product of his speculative imagination.
Thus, these social scientists
argue that the overarching view called relativism is the only
logical one to adopt when we study the body of social science research (or all
research in all fields, for that matter). We can try to observe human societies
and the belief systems they instill in their members (Western science being
just one example of a belief system), but we can’t pretend to do the work
objectively. We come to it with eyes already programmed to notice in the
details around us the patterns we consider “significant”. We see as we do
because of the beliefs we absorbed as children. Every scientist’s model of what
the world is lies deeper than her/his ability to articulate thoughts or
even just observe. Cultural biases can’t be suspended; they prefigure our
ability to think at all.
The whole of reality is
much more detailed and complex than the set of sights, sounds, etc. any one of
us is paying attention to. Other folk from other cultures notice different
details and construct their own pictures of reality, some of them radically
different from ours, but still quite workable.
In short, any human view of
the world, and especially any culture-wide model believed and used by any human
society, is inherently biased. This is the stance taken by the most adamant of
social scientists: even Physics is made of opinions.
Some social scientists go
so far as to claim there aren’t really any “facts” in any of our descriptions of
past events or even of events happening around us. There are only various sets
of details noticed by some of us; these are filtered by values and concepts we
learned as children. Within each culture, people group these details to form a “narrative”.
But as we go from culture to culture, we see that any one of these various
narratives is as valid as any other.
So, at the level of large
generalizations about what “right” and “wrong” are, social scientists not only
have nothing to say, they insist that nothing objectively true can be
said. “Science” is just a Euro-based set of theories that seem to work most of
the time. For now.
Scientists in the
sciences other than the social ones continue to assert there is an empirical,
material reality out there that is common for us all and Science is the most
reliable way we have to understand that reality. But in all branches of Science,
scientists admit that they can’t give a very good explanation or model of what
“right” and “wrong” are – if such things can even be said to exist.
In a further rebuttal of
relativism, however, scientists in the hard sciences and life sciences assert
that the idea that Science can’t give us any reliable insights into how any parts of the world work is nonsense.
Science works. Its successes have been so large and so many that no sane person
can doubt that claim.
In this complex picture
lies the dilemma of the West in modern times. Back and forth, these arguments
called the Science Wars continue
to rage. I’ve touched on a few of them, but there’s not enough space here to go
into even five percent of the whole controversy.
So what’s the bottom
line? The point of all the discussion so far in this chapter?
The point is that Yeats
was right: the best really can lack all conviction. They can even reject the
whole idea of anyone having any “moral convictions” ever. Thus, many social
scientists can read about customs like honor killings and remark, “Well,
that’s their culture.” In fact, for many thinkers today in the universities,
all convictions are temporary and local. (A more sensible compromise position
is taken by Harris in Theories of Culture in Postmodern Times.5)
This has been the
scariest consequence of the rise of Science: moral confusion and indecision in
first, our intellectual elites, then, the whole of Western society. This
confusion began to become serious in the West in the nineteenth century, after
Darwin and the granddaddy of all relativists, Nietzsche. But here we are in the
twenty-first century, and the crisis of moral confidence is getting worse. No educated
person in the West wants to say what “right” is anymore.
Now, all of this
still may sound far removed from the lives of ordinary folk, but the truth is that
relativism’s effect on ordinary people’s lives is crucial. When a society’s
sages can’t guide its people, the people look elsewhere for moral leaders. When
the wise respond to their fellow citizens’ queries about morality with jargon
and equivocation, others – some very unwise – move in to fill the demand in the
ideas marketplace.
So, now we must ask:
how has this moral paralysis since Darwin and Freud affected ordinary folk? How
has the eroding of our old moral codes affected real people’s lives? What consequences
did people who lived in the morally emptiness of the last hundred years have to
endure?
Notes
1. Ruth
Benedict, “Anthropology and the Abnormal,” Journal of General
Psychology, 10 (1934).
2. Thomas Kuhn, The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 3rd ed., 1996).
3. John Searle, Minds,
Brains and Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984).
4. Harold
Kincaid, Philosophical Foundations of the Social Sciences: Analyzing
Controversies in Social Research, (New York, NY: Cambridge University
Press, 1996).
5. Marvin
Harris, Theories of Culture in Postmodern Times (Walnut Creek,
CA: AltaMira Press, 1999).
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.