Chapter 10. (conclusion)
The response in defense of Bayesianism is
complex, but not that complex. What the critics seem not to grasp is the spirit of
Bayesianism. In the Bayesian way of seeing reality and our relationship to it,
everything in the human mind is morphing and floating. The Bayesian picture of
the mind sees us as testing, reassessing, and updating all our ways of understanding
reality all the time.
In the formula above, the term for my
degree of confidence in the evidence, when I take only my background beliefs as
true – i.e. Pr(E/B) – is never 100%. Not even for
very familiar old evidence. Nor is the term for my degree of confidence in the
evidence if I include the hypothesis in my set of mental assumptions – Pr(E/H&B) –
ever equal to 100%. I am never perfectly certain of anything, not of my background
assumptions and not even physical evidence I have seen repeatedly with my own
eyes.
To closely consider this situation in
which a hypothesis is used to try to explain old evidence, we need to examine
the kinds of things that occur in the mind of a researcher in both the
situation in which the new hypothesis does fit the old evidence and the one in
which it doesn’t.
When a hypothesis explains some old
evidence, what the researcher affirms is that, in the term Pr(E/H&B), the
evidence fits the hypothesis, the hypothesis fits the evidence, and the
background assumptions can be integrated with the hypothesis in a comprehensive
way. The researcher is delighted to see that committing to this hypothesis, and
the theory underlying it, will provide reassurance that the old evidence did
happen in the way in which the researcher and her colleagues observed it. In
short, they can feel reassured that they did the work well. The researcher
did not make any mistakes. The researcher really did see what she thought she
did.
Fear of making an observation mistake haunts
scientists. It's reassuring for them when they more confidently can tell
themselves that they didn't mess up. All these logical and psychological
factors raise the researcher’s confidence that this new hypothesis, and the
theory behind it, must be right when he sees it explain problematic old
evidence.
This insight into the workings of Bayesian
confirmation theory becomes even clearer when we consider what the researcher
does when she finds that a hypothesis does not successfully account for the old
evidence. In research, only rarely does a researcher in this situation simply
drop the new hypothesis. Instead, the researcher usually examines the
hypothesis, the old evidence, and her background assumptions to see whether any
of them may be adjusted, using new concepts involving newly proposed variables
or closer observations of the old evidence, so that all the elements in the
Bayesian equation may be brought into harmony again. The researcher gives the
hypothesis thorough consideration. Every chance to prove itself.
When the old evidence is examined in light
of the new hypothesis, if the hypothesis successfully explains that old
evidence, the researcher’s confidence in the hypothesis and confidence
in that old evidence both go up. Even if prior confidence in that old evidence
was really high, the researcher can now feel more confident that she and her
colleagues – even ones in the distant past – did observe that old evidence
correctly and did record their observations well.
The value of this successful application
of the new hypothesis to the old evidence may be small. Perhaps it raises the E
in the term Pr(E/H&B) only a fraction of 1 percent. But
that is still a positive increase in the value of the whole term, and therefore
it supports the hypothesis/theory being considered.
Meanwhile, Pr(H/E&B), i.e.
the scientist’s degree of confidence in the truth of the new hypothesis, also
goes up another notch as a result of the increase in her confidence in the old evidence.
A scientist, like all of us, finds reassurance in the feeling of mental harmony
that comes when more of her perceptions, memories, and concepts about reality
are brought into consonance with each other. (She feels relieved whenever
her cognitive dissonance drops a bit.)
A human mind experiences cognitive
dissonance when it keeps observing evidence that does not fit any of its
models. A person attempting to explain old evidence that is inconsistent with
his worldview sometimes clings to his background beliefs and shuts out the new
theory his colleagues are discussing. He keeps insisting that this new evidence
can’t be correct. Some systemic error must be leading other researchers to
think they have observed E, but they must be mistaken. E is
not what they say it is. “That can’t be right,” he says.
In the meantime, his subversive colleague
down the hall, even if only in her own mind, is arguing “I know what I saw. I
know how careful I’ve been. E is right. Thus, the probability
of H, at least in my mind, has grown. It’s such a relief to
see a way out of the cognitive dissonance I’ve been experiencing for the last
few months. I get it now. Wow, this feels good!” Settling a score with a
stubborn bit of old evidence that refused to fit into any of a scientist’s
models of reality is a bit like finally whipping a bully who picked on her in
elementary school – not really logical, but still very satisfying.
Normally, testing a new theory involves devising
a hypothesis based on that theory and then doing an experiment that will test the
hypothesis. If the experiment delivers the evidence that was predicted by the
hypothesis, but not predicted by my background concepts, then the theory that
the hypothesis is based on seems to me more likely to be true.
But I may also decide to try to use a hypothesis and the theory it is based on to explain some problematic old evidence. If I find that the theory does explain that problematic old evidence, what I’m confirming is not just the hypothesis and its base theory. I have also found a consistency between the old evidence, the new theory/hypothesis, and all or nearly all of my background concepts. (Sadly, at least some of the time, it is likely that I will have to drop a few of my old ways of thinking to make room for the new theory.)
This is why a new theory/hypothesis
explaining some problematic old evidence so deeply affects how much we believe
in the new theory. Our human feelings are engaged and reassured when the new
theory relieves some of our cognitive dissonance. The exhilaration we feel
mostly isn’t logical. But it is human.
And no, it is not obvious that evidence
seen with my own eyes is ever 100% reliable, not even if I’ve seen a particular
phenomenon repeated many times. Neither my familiar background concepts nor the
sense data I see in everyday experiences are trusted that much. If they were,
then I and anyone who trusts gravity, light, and human anatomy would be unable
to watch a good magic show without having a nervous breakdown. Elephants
disappear, men float, and women get sawn in half. If my most basic concepts
were believed at the 100% level, then either I’d have to gouge my eyes out or
go mad.
But I know the magic is a trick of some
kind. And I choose, for the duration of the show, to suspend my desire to
harmonize all my sense data with my set of background concepts. It is supposed
to be a performance of fun and wonder. If I figure out and explain how the
trick is done, I ruin my grandkids’ fun …and my own.
It’s important to point out here that the
idea behind H&B, the set of the new hypothesis/theory plus my
background concepts, is also more complex than the equation can capture. This
part of the formula should be read: “If I integrate the hypothesis into my
whole background concept set.” The formula attempts to capture in symbols
something that is almost not capturable. This is because the point of positing
a hypothesis, H, is that it doesn’t fit neatly
into my background set of beliefs. It is built around a new way of
comprehending reality and thus, it will only be fully integrated into my old
background set of concepts and beliefs if some of those old concepts are
adjusted by careful, gradual tinkering, and some are removed entirely.
Similarly, in the term Pr(H/E&B),
E&B is trying to capture something no math term can
capture. E&B is trying to say: “If I take both the
evidence and my set of background beliefs to be 100% reliable.”
But that way of stating the E&B part
of the term merely highlights the issue of problematic old evidence. This
evidence is problematic because I can’t make it consistent
with all of my background concepts and beliefs, no matter how I tinker with
them.
All the whole formula really does is try
to capture the gist of human thinking and learning. It is a useful metaphor;
but we can’t become complacent about this formula for the Bayesian model of
human thinking and learning any more than we can become complacent about any of
our concepts. And that thought is consistent with the spirit of Bayesianism. It
tells us not to become too blindly attached to any of our concepts, not even
how we think about how we think. Any of them may have to be updated and revised
at any time.
For all these reasons, the criticism of
Bayesianism which says it can’t explain why we find a fit between a hypothesis
and some problematic old evidence reassuring turns out not to be a fatal
criticism at all. It is more a useful mental tool, one that we may use to
deepen our understanding of the Bayesian model.
The Bayesian model tells us to accept that
all the patterns of neuron firings in the brain – i. e. all the hypotheses, bits
of evidence, and background concepts – are forming, reforming, aligning,
realigning, and floating in and out of one another all the time – even concepts
as basic as the ones we have about gravity, matter, space, and time. This whole
view of “Bayesianism” arises if we simply apply Bayesianism to itself.
In short, Bayesianism says we keep
adjusting our thinking until we die.
The Bayesian way of thinking about our own
thinking requires us to be willing to float all our concepts, even our most
deeply held ones. Some are more central, and we use them more often with more confidence.
A few we may believe almost absolutely. But none of our concepts is
irreplaceable.
For humans, the mind is our means of
surviving. Thus, it will adapt to almost anything. Let war, famine, plague,
economics, and technology do what they will. Rattle our living styles and ways until
they tumble. We adjust. We go on.
We gamble heavily on the concepts we
routinely use to organize our sense data and memories of sense data. I use my
concepts to organize the memories already stored in my brain, and the new sense
data that are flooding into my brain, all the time. I keep trying to learn more
concepts – including concepts for organizing other concepts – that will enable
me to utilize my memories more efficiently to make faster, better decisions and
to act more and more effectively. In this constant, restless, searching mental
life of mine, I never trust anything absolutely.
But I choose to stand by my most basic concepts
even at a magic show, not because I am certain they’re right, but because they’ve
been tested and found effective over so many trials for so long that I’m
willing to keep gambling on them. At least until someone proposes something
even more promising to me. I don’t know for certain that the theories of the
real world that my culture has programmed into me are sure bets; they just seem
very likely to be the most promising options available to me now. And I need
some theories about space, matter, etc. every day. I have to see and act. I
can’t live by sitting catatonic.
Harry Houdini
with his “disappearing” elephant, Jennie
(credit:
Wikimedia Commons)
Life is constantly making demands on me to
move and keep moving. I have to gamble on some models of reality just to live
my life; I go with my best horses, my most successful and trusted concepts. And
sometimes I change my mind.
This flexibility on my part is not
weakness or lack of discipline; it is just life. Bayesianism tells us Kuhn’s
thesis in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Sometimes as
individuals, and sometimes as whole tribes, we are constantly adjusting all our
concepts as we try to make our ways of dealing with reality more effective.
And when a researcher begins to grasp a
new hypothesis and the theory it is based on, the resulting experience is like
a religious “awakening” – profound, even life-altering. Everything changes when
we accept a new model or theory because we change. How we perceive and think
changes. In order to “get it”, we have to change. We have to eliminate some old
beliefs from our familiar background belief set and literally see in a new way.
And what of the shifting nature of our
view of reality and the gambling spirit that is implicit in the Bayesian model?
The general tone of all our experiences tells us this overall view of our world
and ourselves – though it may seem scary, or maybe, for confident individuals, exhilarating
– is just life.
We have now arrived at a point where we
can feel confident that Bayesianism gives us a good base on which to build
further reasoning. 100% reliable? No. But solid enough to use and so to
get on with all the other thinking that must be done. It can answer its
critics – both those who attack it with real-world counterexamples and those
who attack it with pure logic. And it outperforms both Rationalism and
Empiricism every time.
Bayesianism is not logically unshakable.
But in a sensible view of our world and ourselves, Bayesianism serves well.
First, because it makes sense when it is applied to our real problem-solving
behavior; second, because it works even when it is applied to itself; third,
because we must have a foundational belief of some kind in place in order to
get on with building a universal moral code; and fourth, because – as was shown
earlier – we have to build that new code. That task is crucial. Without a new
moral code, we aren’t going to survive.
We are now at a good place to pause to
summarize our case so far. The next chapter is devoted to that summing up.
Notes
1. 1. Thomas
Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 3rd ed., 1996).
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.