Tuesday 15 April 2014

Chapter 6  The First Attack On Bayesianism And How It Is Answered

Part A


The idea behind Bayesianism is straightforward enough to be grasped by nearly all adults in any land. But the idea of radical Bayesianism escapes us. All that you do, mentally, fits inside the Bayesian model, but it is very human to dread such a view of oneself and to slip into thinking radical Bayesianism must be wrong. We want desperately to find at least a few ideas that are unshakeable. Too often, unfortunately, people do think that they have found one. But to a true Bayesian, the one truth that he believes is probably absolute is the one that says there are no absolute truths.

An idea is a tool, an application, that enables you to sort, and respond to, sensory experiences – single ones or whole categories of them. When you find an idea that works, you keep it. What can confuse and confound this whole picture is the way that, in the case of some of your most deeply held ideas, you didn’t find them. They came in a trial and error way to some of your ancestors, who then did their best to program these ideas into your parents, who then did their best to program them into you.

Every new idea that you acquire gets installed as part of your mental equipment, after careful Bayesian observations and calculations, either by this process of your own noticing, speculating, and testing, or by your family and your tribe programming you with the idea because the tribe’s early leaders acquired that idea by the first process. Consciousness and even sanity are constantly evolving for all humans, all of the time. We keep re-writing our concept sets, from complex ideas like "justice" and "love" to basic ideas like "up" and "down". (The individual human mind can indeed be made to re-program its notions of “up” and “down”.) (1.) The barest “you” that you are is a dynamic, self-referencing system that is constantly checking your sense perceptions against your ideas about what reality should be and then updating and re-writing itself all of the time.  

And a short side note is in order here. There are a few commonly used, species-wide ideas, or proto-ideas, that you don't "acquire" by either of the above methods because these ideas are hard-wired in at birth. These are not programmed into a human by his tribe nor by his own learning so they don't fit into either of the categories just described. But they do fit inside the modern empiricist view of what knowledge is simply because in the modern empiricist view, with the models it has gained from Biology and especially from Genetics, these built-in ideas are seen as genetically-programmed physiological processes and, thus, subjects for study by geneticists or neurophysiologists. In short, scientists can go looking for them, and they do.

For example, some basic ideas of language are built into all humans, but the genes involved that, during the normal growth of a fetus, cause it to build the language centers in the developing brain, are still being identified. In addition, the structures and functions of these brain areas, once they're built, are only poorly understood. In our present discussion, however, these questions can be passed by. They are biological rather than ideological in nature and, therefore, outside of our present scope. These genes and the brain structures that are built from their coded information might someday even be manipulated, either by genetic engineering or some kinds of behavior modifications involving operant conditioning, surgery, drugs, or other technologies we cannot now even imagine.

But whether such actions will be judged right or wrong, and so will be permitted inside of the normal institutions of our society, will depend on our moral values. These, as we have already seen, are going to need something more to them than what is offered by Empiricism. In fact, as its own moral guide, Empiricism has proved neither logically sound in theory nor effective in practice. The evidence of recent human history strongly suggests that Science can't be its own moral guide. This line of thought returns us to our task – rational discussion of moralities and their sources – and so back to Bayesianism.

So let me reiterate: we are nearly all, nearly all of the time, Bayesians. When an old idea no longer works, we seek by Bayesian ways to find a better idea.
          
This Bayesian model of how we think is so radical that at first it eludes us. The idea that I am adjusting my whole mindset all of the time, and that no parts of it, not even my deepest ideas of who I am or what reality is, are ever fully established or reliable is disturbing, to say the least. But this view is the one I arrive at when I look back over the changes that I have undergone in my own life. The Bayesian model of how a “self” is formed and how it evolves fits the set of memories that I call “myself” exactly.

          Thomas Kuhn

   
Thomas Kuhn was the most famous of the philosophers who have examined the processes by which people adopt a new theory, model, or way of knowing. (2.) His studies focused only on how scientists adopt a new model, but his conclusions can be applied to all human thinking. His most famous book proposes that all of our ways of knowing, even our most cherished ones, are tentative and arbitrary. Under his model of how human knowledge grows, humans advance from an obsolete idea or model to a newer, more comprehensive one by "paradigm shifts", i.e. leaps and starts, rather than in a steady march of gradually growing enlightenment. You "get", and then start to think under, a new model for organizing your thoughts by a kind of conversion experience, not by a gradual process of persuasion and growing understanding. 

It is all very disconcerting. Caution and unrelenting vigilance seem to be the only rational attitudes to take under such a view of the universe and the human place in it. 
  
Of course, to many people, the idea that all of the mind's systems and systems for organizing systems, and perhaps even its overriding operating system, its sanity, are tentative and are subject to constant revision seems disturbing; some prefer to label it “absurd”. But then again, cognitive dissonance theory would lead us to predict that humans would quickly dismiss such a scary picture of themselves. We don't like to see ourselves as lacking in any unshakable principles or beliefs, changing and evolving from stage to stage in life. But evidence and experience suggest that we are indeed almost completely lacking in such fixed principles or beliefs, and we do nearly always evolve personally in those ways. (Why I say "nearly" always will become clear shortly.)

Now at this point in the discussion, opponents of Bayesianism begin to marshall their forces. These critics of Bayesianism give several varied reasons for disagreeing with the Bayesian model, but I want to deal with just two, two of the most telling, one for practical, evidence-based reasons and the other, in the next chapter, for purely theoretical reasons.
 
In the first place, say the critics, Bayesianism simply can’t be an accurate model of how human beings think because humans violate Bayesian principles of rationality every day. Every day, we commit acts that are at odds with what both reasoning and experience have shown us is rational. Some societies still execute their worst criminals. Men continue to bully and exploit women. Adults spank children. We do these things even when all of the research indicates that such behavior is counter-productive.

We fear people who look different than we do on no other grounds than that they look different than we do. We shun them even when we have evidence which shows that there are many trustworthy individuals in that other group and many untrustworthy ones in the group of people who look like us.


Over and over, we act in ways that are not logical by Bayesian standards. We stake the best of our human and material resources on ways of behaving that both reasoning and evidence say are not likely to work. Can Bayesianism account for these glaring bits of evidence that are inconsistent with its model of human thinking?



Notes 

1.http://www.academia.edu/4029955/Degenaar2013_Through_the_Inverting_Glass

2. Kuhn, Thomas; "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"; University of Chicago; 1996

No comments:

Post a Comment

What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.