Chapter 11. Part B
Therefore, in
Western history, the next important world view is the Roman one. Operating
under it, people in general became even more practical, more focused on
physical effectiveness and power, and less interested in, or even aware of,
ideas considered for their own sake. This feeling expressed itself among many
of the early Romans simply and directly in an out-and-out hatred for all things
Greek; the truth was that the Romans borrowed much from the Greeks, especially
in theoretical knowledge, but many Romans loathed having to admit it.
The Romans in their
heyday no longer feared the gods in the way that the ancient Greeks and the
Romans’ own ancestors once had. As the Roman Republic faded and the Roman Empire took over,
the Romans went so far from that way of thinking that they lost much of the Greek,
especially the Athenian, capacity for the things called “abstract” – wonder,
idealism, pure geometry, philosophical speculation, and flights of imagination.
The Romans built their state on Athenian-style, democratic principles, values,
and behaviors, but they also, more like the Spartans, loved practical results and power,
not abstract speculation.
Pont
du Gard: Roman aqueduct (in present day France)
It is tempting here to see
in Roman culture a synthesis of the ways of the Athenians and those of the
Spartans/Macedonians. This would be an example of Hegel’s famous dialectic. One way of
thinking, along with the human groups that gather around it, forms and grows,
and then an opposite way of thinking rises up like a kind of cosmic response to
the first way. The two struggle, interact, and finally meld into a true
synthesis, which is not like a compromise because it is a new way with a life and identity of its own.
The people who are born into the
new way are not aware of using some elements from one philosophy and some from
the other. The new way is simply their way, and the supporting ideas that are
added to the new system make it seem like a neat, smooth, seamless whole.
Thesis, antithesis, then synthesis, over and over, with the system always
spiraling up toward greater and greater consciousness. This is Hegel’s model of
human social evolution.
It is tempting. It’s a fairly simple model
and with a little stretching it can be made to at least seem to fit in era
after era and country after country when we study human history. But it is simply
too simple. The Roman way of thinking and way of life did contain some ideals
similar to those of the Athenians and some like those of the Spartan ones, but
there was too much else going on in the thinking and living styles of the
Romans for us to be satisfied with Hegel’s model. Human societies are subtler
than that. What makes more sense is to look at each society and see what its
world view, values, morés, and behavior patterns were like and how they
coordinated in the lives of the people who operated under them to produce a
whole culture and way of life that met the survival demands of the time. Using that humbler, but subtler and more nuanced, model, we can learn about how human societies really work.
The point is that the model of
human cultural evolution presented in this book doesn’t attempt to be as all-encompassing
as Hegel’s thesis-antithesis-synthesis model because the real process of human
cultural evolution doesn’t fit that model. Rather, the real process of human
cultural evolution is more closely analogous to the process of evolution in the
rest of nature, by genetic variation and natural selection and accident and
disaster.
Life didn’t move forward through time and
proliferate into its many forms by the mechanism that Hegel describes. In the
past, conditions in the non-living world like tsunamis, earthquakes, floods,
droughts, volcanic eruptions, and even collisions with giant meteors suddenly
closed down, or opened up, reams of opportunities in the living world. Then, usually, life forms moved
in opportunistically. Life spreads across time and space not like a chain or a
road or a ladder, but like a stream branching and bifurcating over and over onward
from that primal source started from a few cells long ago. And it is also important to emphasize that the direction of growth, in the living world, is against the flow of entropy. Life flows "uphill". The direction of living flow is from the source into the branches, not the other way round.
The model of human cultural evolution
presented in this book can’t match Hegel’s dialectic for cognitive
attractiveness. Hegel’s model seems so neat and complete. But life isn’t that
neat, and it is in the realm of the living that our models of human culture
must be placed. The model that we are going to explore here can do what we need
it to do. It can give us enough insights into how human cultures work, and what
right and wrong are, both apparently and really, for us to then be able to
build a rational moral code. And that is all we need.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.