Albert Einstein and Kurt Gödel
For
years, the most optimistic of the empiricists were looking to AI for models of
thinking that would work in the real world. Their position has been cut down in
several ways since those early days. What exploded it for many was the proof
found by Kurt Gödel, Einstein’s companion during his lunch hour walks at
Princeton. Gödel showed that no rigorous system of symbols for expressing the
most basic of human thinking routines can be a complete system. (In Gödel’s proof, the ideas he analyzed were
basic axioms in arithmetic.) Gödel’s
proof is difficult for laypersons to follow, but non-mathematicians don’t need
to be able to do that formal logic in order to grasp what his proof implies
about everyday thinking. (See Hofstadter for an accessible critique of Gödel.10)
Douglas Hofstadter
If
we take what it says about arithmetic and extend that finding to all kinds of
human thinking, Gödel’s proof says no symbol system exists for expressing our
thoughts that will ever be good enough to allow us to express and discuss all
the new ideas human minds can dream up. Furthermore, in principle, there can’t ever
be any such system of expression.
What
Gödel’s proof suggests is that no way of modelling the human mind will ever
adequately explain what it does. Not in English, Logic, French, Russian,
Chinese, Java, C++, music, or Martian. We will always be able to generate
thoughts, questions, and statements that we can’t express in any one symbol
system. If we find a system that can be used to encode some of our favorite
ideas really well, we will only discover that no matter how well the system is
designed, no matter how large or subtle it is, we will have other thoughts that
we can’t express at all in that system. Yet we have to make statements that at
least attempt, more or less adequately, to communicate our ideas.
Science, like most human endeavors, is social. It has to be shared in order to advance.
Science, like most human endeavors, is social. It has to be shared in order to advance.
Other
theorems in computer science offer support to Gödel’s theorem. For example, in
the early days of the development of computers, programmers were continually creating
programs with loops in them. After a program had been written, when it was run
it would sometimes become stuck in a subroutine that would repeat a sequence of
steps from, say, line 193 to line 511 then back to line 193, again and again.
Whenever a program contained this kind of flaw, a human being had to stop the
computer, go over the program, find why the loop was occurring, then either
rewrite the loop or write around it. The work was frustrating and time
consuming.
Soon,
a few programmers got the idea of writing a kind of meta-program they hoped
would act as a check. It would scan other programs, find their loops, and fix
them, or at least point them out to programmers so they could be fixed. The
programmers knew that writing such a program would be difficult, but once it
was written, it would save many people a great deal of time.
Alan Turing winning a race ( He was a world class athlete as well as mathematician.)
However,
progress on the writing of this check program encountered difficulty after
difficulty. Eventually, Alan Turing, a man adept at computer languages, published
a proof showing that writing a check program was, in principle, not possible. A
foolproof algorithm for checking other algorithms is, in principle, not
possible. (See “Halting Problem” in Wikipedia.11)
This finding in computer science, the science
many people see as our bridge between the abstractness of thinking and the
concreteness of material reality, is Gödel all over again. In another kind of
proof, it confirms our deepest feelings about empiricism. It is doomed to
remain incomplete. No completely effective check program has ever been found. Programs
that are able to catch beginner programmers’ simpler mistakes have been
written, but no foolproof one has ever been created in any of the many
programming languages that have evolved in the field over the years.
The
possibilities for arguments and counter-arguments on this topic in AI are
fascinating, but for our purposes in trying to find a base for a philosophical
system and a moral code, the conclusion is much simpler. The more we study both
the theoretical points and the real-world evidence, including evidence from science
itself, the more we’re driven to conclude that the empiricist way of seeing or
understanding what thinking and knowing are will probably never be able to
explain itself. If Gödel’s proof is right, and nearly every expert in math and computer
science thinks it is, and if it is extended to human thinking in general, empiricism’s
own methods have ruled out the possibility of an unshakeable empiricist
beginning point for epistemology.
If I
think I have found a way to describe what thinking is, then I will have to
express what I want to say about the matter in a language of some kind—English,
Russian, C++, or some other kind of language for encoding thoughts. But there
is not, nor can there be, a code that is capable of capturing and communicating
what the thinker is doing as she is thinking about her own thinking. It is a
mental conundrum with no solution. (What is the meaning of the word meaning?)
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.