Now,
at this point in the discussion, opponents of Bayesianism begin to marshal
their forces. Critics of Bayesianism give several varied reasons for continuing
to disagree with the Bayesian model, but I want to deal with just two of the
most telling—one is practical and evidence-based, and the other, which I’ll
discuss in the next chapter, is purely theoretical.
Elizabeth Eckerd (center) being taunted in Arkansas, 1957
In
the first place, say the critics, Bayesianism simply can’t be an accurate model
of how humans think because humans violate Bayesian principles of rationality
every day. Every day, we commit acts that are at odds with what both reasoning
and experience have shown us is rational. Some societies still execute criminals.
Men continue to bully and exploit, even beat, women. Some adults still spank
children. We fear people who look different from us on no other grounds than
that they look different from us. We shun them even when we have evidence
showing there are many trustworthy individuals in that other group and many
untrustworthy ones in the group of people who look like us. We do these things
even when research indicates that such behaviour and beliefs are counterproductive.
Over
and over, we act in ways that are illogical by Bayesianism’s own standards. We
stake the best of our human and material resources on ways of behaving that
both reasoning and evidence say are not likely to work. Can Bayesianism account
for these glaring bits of evidence that are inconsistent with its model of
human thinking?
The
answer to this critique is disturbing. The problem is not that the Bayesian
model doesn’t work as an explanation of human behaviour and thinking. The
problem is rather that the Bayesian model of human thinking and the behaviours
driven by that thinking works too well. The irrational behaviours individual humans
engage in are not proof of Bayesianism’s inadequacy, but rather proof of how it
applies to the thinking, learning, and behaviour of individuals and also to the
thinking, learning, and behaviour of whole communities and even whole nations.
Societies
evolve and change because they each contain some people who are naturally
curious. These curious people constantly imagine and test new ideas and new
ways of doing things like obtaining food, raising kids, fighting off invaders,
healing the sick—any of the things the society must do in order to carry on. Often,
other subgroups in society view any new idea or way of doing things as
threatening to their most deeply held beliefs. If the adherents of the new idea
keep demonstrating that their idea works and that the more intransigent group’s
old ways are obsolete, then the larger society will usually marginalize the
less effectual members and their system of ideas. In this way, a society
mirrors what an individual does when he finds a better way of growing onions or
teaching kids or easing Papa’s arthritic pain. In this way, we adapt—as
individuals, but more profoundly, as societies—to new lands and markets and to
new technologies such as vaccinations, cars, televisions, computers, and so on.
Farmers, cooks, and teachers who cling to obsolete methods are simply passed
by, eventually even by their own grandchildren.
But
then there are the more disturbing cases, the ones that caused me to write nearly always above. Sometimes large
minorities or even majorities of citizens hang on to obsolete concepts and ways.
The
Bayesian model of human thinking works well, most of the time, to explain how
individuals form and evolve their basic idea systems. Most of the time, it also
can explain how a whole community, tribe, or nation can grow and change its
sets of beliefs, thinking styles, customs, and practices. But can it account
for the times when majorities in a society do not embrace a new way in spite of
the Bayesian calculations showing the idea is sound? In short, can the Bayesian
model explain the dark side of tribalism?
Nazi party rally, 1938. Tribalism at its worst
As
we saw in our last chapter, for the most part, individuals become willing to
drop a set of ideas that seems to be losing its effectiveness when they also
encounter a new set of ideas that looks more promising. They embrace the new
ideas that perform well, that guide the individual well through the hazards of real
life. Similarly, at the tribal level, whole societies usually drop paradigms,
and the ways of thinking and living based on those paradigms, when the citizens
repeatedly see that the old ideas are no longer working and that a set of new
ideas is getting better results. Sometimes, on the level of radical social change,
this mechanism can cause societies to marginalize or ostracize subcultures that
refuse to let go of the old ways. Cars and car people marginalized the horse
culture within a generation. Assembly line factories brought the unit cost of
goods down until millions who had once accepted that they would never have a
car or a t.v. bought one on payments and owned it in two years. The old small
scale shop in which a team of sixteen men made whole cars, one at a time, was obsolete.
The
point is that when a new subculture with new beliefs and ways keeps getting
good results, and the old subculture keeps proving ineffectual by comparison,
the majority usually do make the switch to the new way—of chipping flint,
growing corn, spearing fish, making arrows, weaving cloth, building ships,
forging gun barrels, dispersing capital to the enterprises with the best growth
potential, or connecting a computer to the Internet.
It
is also important to state here that, for most new paradigms and practices, the
tests applied to them over the decades only confirm that the old way is still
better. Most new ideas are tested and found to be less effective than the
established ones. Only rarely does a superior one come along.
But
the more crucial insight is the one that comes next. Sometimes, if a new
paradigm challenges a tribe’s most sensitive central beliefs, the Bayesian
calculations about what individuals and their society will do next break down,
and most tribes continue to adhere to the old beliefs. The larger question here
is whether the Bayesian model of human thinking, when it is taken up to the
level of human social evolution, can account for these apparently un-Bayesian
behaviors.
Many
of our most deeply held beliefs concern areas of our lives that govern our
interactions with other humans—family members, friends, neighbors, colleagues,
and fellow citizens. These are areas we have long seen, and mostly still see,
as being guided not by reason but by sensitive moral beliefs—beliefs derived in
different ways from those about the physical world. In anthropological terms,
these are the beliefs that enable the members of the tribe to live together, interact,
work in teams, and get along.
The continued
exploitation of women and execution of murderers mentioned above are
consequences of the fact that in spite of our worries about the failures of our
moral code in the last hundred years, much of that code lingers on. In many
aspects of our lives, we are still drifting with the ways that were familiar,
even though our confidence in those ways is eroding around us. We don’t know
what else to do. In the meantime, these traditional ways are so deeply
ingrained and familiar as to seem natural for many people, even automatic, in
spite of evidence to the contrary.
When
we study the deepest and most profound of these “traditional” behaviors and
beliefs, we are dealing with those beliefs that are most powerfully programmed
into every child by all of the tribe’s adult members. These beliefs aren’t
subject to the Bayesian models and laws that usually govern the learning
processes of the individual human. In fact, they are almost always viewed by
the individual as the most important parts of his culture and himself. They are
guarded in the psyche by emotional associations that elicit anger and fear when
disturbed. They are the beliefs and morés your parents, teachers, storytellers,
and leaders enjoined you to hang on to at all cost. In fact, for most people in
most societies, these beliefs and the morés that emerge from them are seen as
being simply normal. Varying from them is abnormal.
artist's conception of Moses receiving 10 commandments from God
For
centuries, in the West, our moral meta-belief—that is to say, our belief about
our moral beliefs—was that they had been set down by God and, therefore, were
universal and eternal. When we took that view, we were in effect placing our
moral beliefs in a separate category from the rest, a category meant to
guarantee their inviolability. Non-Western societies do the same.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.