The third big idea in this analysis of our background assumptions
is one that this book has laboured long to establish. It is the assumption
that says there is a kind of moral order in this universe, a moral order that
is “real” in the sense that scientists mean—observably, empirically real.
The universe runs by laws that produce patterns in the flows of
events, and our culturally acquired moral values guide us, as tribes, to
navigate through those patterns. These values were learned through trial and
error by millions of people over thousands of years. People learned that
certain general ideas called values—large
ideas like courage, wisdom, freedom, and love—work. In theory, many varied
cultures can evolve that incorporate these values into a viable way of life. But
across all of these cultures, large general patterns are discernible. If we go,
as whole societies, in the direction toward which our most basic values point,
we get useful results. The people who live by these values survive. Those who
don’t, don’t.
Values have physically observable effects as real as gravity and
magnetism. Gravity and magnetism are seen by how they affect the movements of
clusters of particles. Values are seen by how they affect the movements of
tribes of people.
Again we can ask about our third idea in this line of thinking: “As
opposed to what?” The usual opposing idea to moral realism in modern times is
moral relativism, under which moral values are mere tastes, and right and wrong
depend on where you are. What was right in Rome in the first century of the
modern era is not morally right today, relativists say; what is right in Africa is not right in Western Europe. Under the moral relativists’
thinking, there is no peaceful way to resolve disputes between different
cultures because there is no common ground on which to even begin the
negotiations.
There are lots of forms of moral relativism being espoused in the
twenty-first century. Some even claim, in convoluted arguments, that they do offer
us ways to establish common definitions of “good” and to resolve disputes
peacefully. But for the purposes of this book, moral relativism as just defined
will suffice. In the end, moral relativism takes the position that moral values
can’t be grounded in any specifiable, physically observable phenomena.7 I claim
that we won’t survive thinking like that, and we don’t have to think like that.
The view of moral realism I
offer in this book says of the relativists’ position that nothing could be
further from the truth. Material reality is the common ground, and if we grasp what our species’ history is telling us about values, we can infer
that values are based on reality, then debate how to interpret that reality,
and then test our various models against the evidence of history. Finally, we
are driven logically to conclude that all of our disputes can be settled peacefully. The things stopping us from creating and maintaining world peace
are the anti-morals: cowardice, cupidity, laziness, and bigotry.
So let us now close in on our long-anticipated main point.
If, as a modern human being in touch with the basics of Science in
all its forms, I believe the universe is one coherent thing—even if all its
laws are not yet understood—and I further believe it is conscious—even if its
consciousness is so vast that it can’t yet be comprehended by humans—and I
further believe it is morally responsive—even if its moral quality is only
discernible in the flows of millions of people over thousands of years—if I
believe these three claims, then in my personal way I do believe in God.
What? That’s it?
Yes, my patient
reader. That’s it. I do still believe in God. My view is a pretty lean
one, but every instinct in me tells me that such is life. Adults have to get by
on leaner fare than children who seek a bearded man in the sky. The best
consolation of adult life is the firm belief that the patterns that we see in the
flows of events in world – even patterns that only show in the evidence of
centuries of human actions – are real. Your deep intuition that “good” and “right” are real
is not naïve or crazy. It’s the sanest belief you have.
And now, in a
personal response to the logic presented so far, let me try to show that this
case is enough to maintain my theism. And personal
is the most honest way to describe my final chapter. It has to be so. Or, to be
exact, it has to make the personal universal and the universal personal, as we
shall see.
Notes
1. Dennis Overbye,
“Laws of Nature, Source Unknown,” New
York Times, December 18, 2007. http://www.nytimes.com/2007/12/18/science/18law.html?
pagewanted=all&_r=0.
2. Homer, The Illiad (c. 800–725 BC; Project Gutenberg),
p. 91. https://www.gutenberg.org/files/6130/6130-h/6130-h.html#fig120.
3. Nicholas Maxwell, From Knowledge to Wisdom: A Revolution for
Science and the Humanities (London,
UK: Pentire Press, 1984), pp. 107–109.
4. http://www.wired.com/2013/12/secret-language-of-plants/
5. Joshua Roebke, “The Reality Tests,” Seed magazine, June 4, 2008. http://seedmagazine.com/content/article/the_reality_tests/P1/.
6. Ibid.
7. Chris Gowans, “Moral Relativism,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2015. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-relativism/.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.