Chapter 4 Finding A Foundation For A Moral Code
If we want to stay
loyal to our Science and even use it to build a new moral code that works,
what we want to know first is how the universe works, i.e. what we must deal with in
the reality Science says is out there. Then, we can use that base and build a
code that will guide us through the universe’s currents with more joy and less
pain. If we get the basics right, we’ll have a reasonable chance of figuring
the other details out. If not, we’ll be doomed to wander off track, into pain
and death.
People who don’t make a desire for real world effectiveness the
primary focus of their thought and lives don’t pass on their values and ways of
living because they die out. People who do strive to find effective ways to
live pay attention to the universe around them and as a result, more frequently survive to transmit
their ways forward in time. Their beliefs and customs survive in their kids.
Therefore, we begin
to build a new moral vision and code, by trying to learn all we can about our
world and our place in it.
However, as we consider
this problem, we see that there is an even deeper problem, namely the
reliability of our basic information-gathering system – i.e. the human brain
and the mind in it. Can we trust the senses we use to gather information about
our world? Then, can we trust our ways of forming concepts about the workings
of the world from our impressions and memories of it?
For example, in the
realm of sensory perceptions, color-blindness renders some people incapable of seeing
subtle differences between shades of red and orange. And color-blindness is
just one of the things that can warp our view of the world even at the sensory
level. Our senses are not perfectly reliable.
Then, biases we learn
as children can make us notice some details and totally miss others. How many
Europeans would spot cougar tracks if they walked by them in a Canadian forest?
A traditional Cree would never miss them. In his world, missing signs that a cougar
is active in his area could cost him his life.
Karl Marx (credit:
Wikimedia Commons)
On the topic of biased
perception, consider the complex example of a girl I knew at university in 1973
whose core beliefs were all Marxist. Her view of reality was totally shaped by
her political ideology. For her, all the world’s troubles were due to
capitalists’ conspiracies; only a world workers’ state could ever create a
decent life for all people. The fact that the communist states of the world
were rife with corruption and cruelty was always due to capitalists in other
lands. Harsh living conditions, secret police, and prison camps in these states
were “temporary”; they would be “remedied” as soon as the capitalists had been “eradicated
from the earth”.
She had so utterly
deluded herself that I used to feel weak as I listened to her. She saw oppression
in the faces of all the workers we passed as we walked the campus. She saw
fascist symbolism in every poster on the notice boards. She carried a list of
government people whom she and her friends were going to assassinate “when the
revolution comes.” Her eyes were working, but what she noticed as she walked
through her day was utterly biased. She was unshakably determined that
everything she experienced in every facet of life must conform to Marxism in
every detail, from atomic to biological to social to cosmic.
But however deluded
she seemed in my eyes, she taught me something: she taught me how profoundly
humans can be led by a flawed idea system to delude themselves even when their
senses are working perfectly.
Since then, of
course, Communism has failed totally; the world has seen that centrally planned
economies wither. But that girl was just one of many sincere, deluded people
I’ve met over the years who left me wondering, “Which of my beliefs can I
trust? Can I trust my moral beliefs? Can I trust my everyday ones? Or even ones
about the physics of reality? Can I even trust what I see?”
Flawed
beliefs about the world can lead us to lives of error and pain. Marxism’s
biggest flaw is its insistence on its own infallibility. This claim taken as an
axiom means that a Marxist workers’ state will tolerate no opposition, no
debate, and no other political parties. Thus, Marxist states create totalitarian
institutions that open the way for tyrants. Over and over, we have seen that once
institutions that enable tyranny are there for the seizing, a “seizer” always
arises.
But Science isn’t
about who the latest seizer is. Science is about the reality that comes before
political thoughts even begin.
Consider a further
example: if we assert, as some Marxists do, that Science is just one more
social construct that must conform to the will of the people, we
inevitably begin to tell our scientists what we want them to conclude, instead
of asking them what the evidence seems to show.
Trofim Lysenko (credit: Wikipedia)
A clear example of a policy that was
flawed from its assumptions on up is the doctrine called Lysenkoism in
Soviet Russia. In that nation in the 1920s, the official state position was
that human nature itself could be altered and humans made into perfect
“socialist citizens” by changing their outward behaviors. If they were made to
act like selfless socialist citizens, they would truly become so, even in their
genes. In fact, all species could be transformed in this same way.
This government position required that
the Darwinian model of evolution be dropped. Dialectical materialism,
Communism’s base, was the true worldview. Under it, physical reality exists as
a projection of the will of the people who have power, whoever that may be. In
a Communist state, the workers get the power, and the political will of the
proletariat can make all things, including physical reality and the human
activity that works to understand it, namely Science.
Darwin had said that members of a
living species do not acquire genetic changes via individual members of the
species having their physical traits altered. Instead, physical traits of a
species change when its gene pool is altered by genetic variation and natural
selection. Therefore, physical changes in a species, in anatomy and physiology,
happen gradually over many generations.
But, in its determination to create its
vision of reality, Communism required people to believe that the acquired characteristics
of any organism – even, for example a cat's being hairless due to its being
shaved every day by its owner – could be inherited by that organism's
descendants.1 Regularly shaved tabby cats, for example, would
have congenitally hairless kittens. For years, Soviet agriculture was crippled by the
Communist Party’s attempts to make its political “truism” be true in real crops
and livestock. In essence, farmers were asked to deny what they were seeing.
Deny reality.
Of course, the Marxist truism simply
wasn’t the case, as many Russians on farms learned, to their sorrow. Reality is
not a projection of the will of the workers, the owners, the aristocrats, the
czar, or anyone else who manages to gain political power. It just is. Crops
failed and livestock died due ultimately to a flawed basic assumption, in the
above case, Lysenkoism.
Consider a few more
basic examples. Even my senses sometimes are not to be trusted. I may believe
that light always travels in straight lines. I may see, half-immersed in a
stream, a stick that looks bent at the water line, so I believe it to be bent.
But when I pull it out, I find that it is straight. If I am a caveman trying to
spear fish in a stream, blind adherence to my concepts about a thing as basic
as light may cause me to starve. I’ll overshoot the fish every time, while the
girl on the other shore, a better learner, cooks her catch.
I can immerse one
hand in snow and keep the other on a hand warmer in my pocket. If I then go
into a cabin to wash my hands in tepid water, one hand senses the water is
cold, the other, that it’s warm. Can’t I trust my own senses?
The examples above
all show how urgent is our need for some solidly reliable core thinking
concepts. Get your beginnings wrong, and everything else you conclude will be
full of flaws.
Thus, the crucial first
question in building a belief system is not “What is true?” but “How can I know
whether my most basic beliefs about reality – i.e. my sense perceptions of my
world – are really true? Is what I see …there?”
How reliable is the sensing/thinking
system I use to observe reality and then to form basic concepts about it? The branch of Philosophy that seeks to answer
these questions is called epistemology. It studies the nature, methods,
and limits of our knowledge – what distinguishes a reliable belief from mere
opinion.
Around our basic
concepts, we build more complex systems of ideas. Basic ideas eventually lead
us to ways of acting and living. Flawed basics lead us into flawed ways of
living that lead us to error, suffering, and death. Knowing these truths about
ourselves should motivate us to try to construct a few fully reliable core concepts.
Then, we can build a reliable moral system around them.
Once we have a basic
set of ideas that we really can trust in place – one that gets past political
ideologies, childhood biases, and even the shortcomings of our senses – then we
may build a moral system we can believe in. In short, in this book we shall aim
to build a moral belief system that from its base to the
principles it gives us to follow in daily life is as logically sound as we can possibly make it. A way of thinking that is
consistent both with the evidence of the real world and with itself.
In order to achieve
that goal, in our next chapter, we shall begin by discussing empiricism,
an epistemology that claims to be built only on observable, real-world evidence,
and to never fall back on assumptions or ideologies of any kind.
The way we begin will determine - to a very high degree - the reliability of what we conclude. The project we are embarking on is the most important one on which we could embark. We must do our very best to get our beginning right.
The way we begin will determine - to a very high degree - the reliability of what we conclude. The project we are embarking on is the most important one on which we could embark. We must do our very best to get our beginning right.
Notes
1. “Lysenkoism,” Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia. Accessed
April 1, 2015.http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lysenkoism.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.