Chapter 3. (continued)
Scientists
now know that most of the concepts we use to recognize and respond to things
are concepts we were taught by the mentors and role models we had as children;
we don’t discover very many concepts on our own. Our childhood programming teaches
us how to cognize things. After that, almost always, we don’t cognize things,
only recognize them. (Why our childhood
mentors programmed us in the ways they did will be explored in upcoming
chapters.)
Empiricists
claim that all human knowing and thinking happens in this way. Watch the world.
Notice the patterns that repeat. Store them up in memories. Pull the memories
out and, when they fit, use them to make smart decisions and react effectively
to life. Remember what works and keep trying. For individuals and nations,
according to the empiricists, that’s how life goes. The most effective way of
human life, the way that makes this common sense process rigorously logical, is
science.
There
are arguments against this way of thinking about thinking and this model of how
human thinking and knowing work. Empiricism is a way of seeing ourselves and our
minds that sounds logical, but it has its problems.
Opponents
of empiricism and science have long asked, “When a human sees things in the
real world and spots patterns in the events going on there, then makes
statements about what she is spotting, what
is doing the spotting? The human mind, and the sense data–processing
programs it must already contain to be able to do the tricks empiricists
describe, obviously came before any data processing could be done. What is this
equipment, and how does it work?”
Philosophers of science have had trouble
explaining what this mind that does the knowing is, and thus what science,
the most rigorous form of knowing, is and is trying to do.
Consider
what science is aiming to achieve. What scientists want to discover, come to
understand, and then use in creative ways in the real world are what are
usually called the “laws of nature”. Scientists do more than simply observe the
events in physical reality. They also strive to understand how these events
come about and then to express what they understand in general statements about
these events, in mathematical formulas, in chemical formulas, in rigorously
logical sentences in one of the world’s many languages, or in some other symbol
system used by people for conveying their thoughts to other humans. A “natural
law” statement must describe one of the ways in which reality works, and, to be
considered scientific, the statement must be set down in such a way that it can
be tested in the real world.
If claims
about this newly discovered real-world truth are going to be worth considering,
scientists must be able to test those claims in some real, material way. Thus,
any natural law statement that is made, to be of any practical use whatever and
to stand any chance of enduring, must first be expressed in some language or
symbol system that humans use to communicate ideas with other humans. A theory
or model that can be expressed only inside the head of its inventor will die
with her or him.
The following is a verbal statement of Newton’s
law of universal gravitation: “Any two bodies in the universe attract each
other with a force that is directly proportional to the product of their masses
and inversely proportional to the square of the distance between them.”
In contrast, the
mathematical formula expressing Newton’s law of universal gravitation looks
like this:
And consider another
example:
The Pythagorean theorem
is a mathematical law, but is it a scientific one? Can it be tested in some
absolutely unshakable way in the real world? (Hint: How can you measure the
sides and know you’re exactly accurate?)
The
big problem occurs when we try to analyze logically just how true statements
like Newton’s laws of motion or Darwin’s theory of evolution are. Do statements
of these laws express unshakeable truths about the real world or are they just temporarily
useful ways of roughly describing what appears to be going on in
reality – ways that are followed for a few decades while the laws appear to
enable scientists to predict events in reality, but that then are revised or
dropped when new problems they can’t explain are encountered?
Many
scientific theories in the last four hundred years have been revised or dropped
altogether. Do we dare to say about any natural law statement that it is true
in the unassailable way in which 5 + 7 = 12 is true or the Pythagorean theorem
is true?
This
debate is a hot one in Philosophy right up to the present time. Many
philosophers of science claim that natural law statements, once they’re
supported by enough experimental evidence, can be considered to be true in the
same way as valid math theorems are. But there are also many who say the
opposite —that all scientific statements are tentative. These people believe
that, given time, all such statements get replaced by new statements based on
new models or theories.
If all
natural law statements are seen as being only temporarily true, then science
can be seen as a kind of fashion show whose ideas have little more shelf life
than the fads in the usual parade of clothes, makeup, hairstyles, television
shows, and songs on the radio. Or put another way, science’s law statements all
become just more narratives, not necessarily true so much as useful, but useful
only in the lands in which they gain some currency and only for limited time
periods at best.
And
the logical flaws that can be spotted in empiricist reasoning are not small
ones.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.