Chapter 7. Part B
One of the ways by which a new hypothesis gets
more respect among the experts who are interested in the field that the
hypothesis covers is by its being able to explain old evidence that no other
theories in the field have been able to explain. For example, physicists all
over the world felt that the probability they assigned in their minds to Einstein’s
Theory of Relativity took a huge jump upward when Einstein used the theory to
account for the changes in the orbit of the planet Mercury - changes that were
familiar to physicists, but that had long defied explanation by the old,
familiar Newtonian model.
representation of the inner solar system
The constant, gradual shift in that
planets’ orbit had baffled astronomers for decades. This shift could not be explained
by any pre-Relativity models. But Relativity Theory could describe this gradual
shift and make predictions about it that were extremely accurate. Instances in other
branches of Science of hypotheses that worked to explain old, anomalous
phenomena could easily be listed. Kuhn, in his book, gives many of them. (1.)
What is wrong with Bayesianism, then,
according to its critics is that it cannot explain why we do give more credence
to a theory when we realize that it can be used to explain pieces of old,
anomalous, evidence that had long defied explanation by the established
theories in the field. When the formula given above is applied to this
situation then, critics say, Pr(E/B) has to be considered to be equal to 100%, or
certainty, since the evidence (E) has been accepted as having been accurately
observed for a long time. After all, it has been replicated many times.
Similarly, Pr(E/H&B) has to be thought of as being equal to 100%, for
the same reasons, because the evidence has been known and has been known to
have been reliably observed and recorded many times since long before we ever
had this new theory to add to our stock of usable ideas. When these two
quantities are put into the equation, again according to the critics, it looks
like this:
Pr(H/E&B) = Pr(H/B)
This new version
of the formula emerges because Pr(E/B) and Pr(E/H&B) are now both equal to 100%, or a probability
of 1, and therefore, they can be canceled out of the equation. But what the new
version of the formula means is that, when I realize that this new theory or
hypothesis that I am thinking about accepting and adding to my mental
programming can be used to solve and explain some old and nagging problems in
my field, my overall confidence in this new theory is not raised at all. The
degree to which I now trust the theory - after seeing it explain some old,
troubling evidence - is equal to the degree to which I trusted it before I
realized that it might apply to, and explain, that same old evidence.
This is simply not what happens in real
life. When we suddenly realize that a new theory/model that we have been testing
can be used to solve some old problems that were previously not solvable, we
are definitely impressed and definitely more inclined to believe that this new
theory or model of reality is a true one.
In other words,
the critics say, Bayesianism, as a way of describing what goes on in human
thinking, is obviously not adequate. It can’t account for some of the ways of
thinking that we know for sure we use. We do indeed test new theories against
old, puzzling evidence all of the time, and we do feel much more impressed with
a new theory if it can fully account for that same puzzling, old evidence.
Notes
1. Kuhn, Thomas;
"The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"; University of Chicago;
1996
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.