Wednesday, 7 January 2015

Chapter 3.            Part D

         If all natural law statements are seen as being only “temporarily true”, then Science can be seen as a kind of fashion show whose fads have a little more shelf life than the fads in the usual parade of clothes, hairstyles, make-up, television shows, and songs on the radio. Or put another way, Science’s “law statements” all become just more “narratives”, not really “true” so much as useful, but useful only in the lands in which they gain some currency and only for limited time periods, at best.
               
            And the logical flaws that can be spotted in empiricist reasoning are not small ones.
               
       Even the terms that natural-law statements contain are vulnerable to attack by the skeptics. Hume argued more than two hundred years ago that we humans can’t really know that any of the laws we think we see in nature are absolutely true because when we state a natural law, the terms that we use to name objects and events that we want to focus on exist only in our minds. A simple statement that seems to us to make sense, like the one that says hot objects will cause us pain if we touch them, can’t be trusted. To assume that this “law” is true is to assume that our definitions for the terms "hot" and "pain" will continue to make sense in the future as they have in the past. But we can’t know that these assumptions will hold in the future. We haven’t been to the future. (Maybe we'll all get enhanced into bionics shortly after birth, and we'll stop feeling pain altogether.)  
   
            Thus, all of the terms in natural law statements, even terms like “protons”, “atoms”, “acids”, “genes”, “cells”, “galaxies”, etc. are fabrications of our minds, terms that we create because they help us to sort and categorize our sensory experiences and memories of sensory experiences and so to talk to each other about what seems to be going on around us. But reality does not contain any things that are somehow qualified naturally as atoms, cells, or galaxies. If you look at a gene, it won’t be wearing a name tag that reads “Gene.” 

            Right from the start, our natural law statements must gamble on the future validity of our current mental categories, i.e. our humanly made-up terms for "things". The terms can seem sound, but they are still gambles, and some that humans once gambled on with great confidence turned later, in the light of new evidence, to be naïve and inadequate. 

                                           

                                                         Isaac Newton

            Newton’s laws of motion are now seen by physicists as being useful, low-level approximations of the subtler, relativistic laws of motion formulated by Einstein. The substance “phlogiston” once seemed to explain all of Chemistry. Then Lavoisier did some experiments which showed phlogiston didn't exist. On the other hand, people spoke of genes long before microscopes which could show them to the human eye were invented, and people still speak of atoms, even though no one has ever seen one. Some terms last because they enable us to build mental models and do experiments that work.  

            But the list of scientific theories that eventually “fell from fashion" is very long.


               
                                                                    Antoine Lavoisier 


            Various further attempts to nail down what scientific thinking does, and to prove that it is a truly reliable way of knowing, have been made in the last hundred years, but they have all come to insoluble conundrums of their own.
               
      The logical positivists, for example, tried to bypass Hume’s problems with the terms in scientific laws and to put the burden of meaning and proof onto whole propositions instead. A key point in the logical positivists’ case is that all meaningful statements are either analytic or synthetic.  Any statement that does not fit into one of these two categories, the positivists say, is irrelevant noise.

            Analytic statements are statements whose truth or falsity is determined by the definitions of the terms that they contain. For example, “All bachelors are unmarried men” is an analytic statement. If we understand the terms in the sentence we can immediately verify, by thinking it through, whether or not the statement is true.

Synthetic statements are ones whose truth or falsity we must work out by referring to evidence found in the real world, not in the statement itself. In Science, the needed evidence is found in human observations of the real world. “All substances contract when cooled” is a synthetic statement (not quite a true one, as observations of water/ice can show). So is “If a creature is a whale, then it is a mammal”.

The logical positivists aimed to show that the talk that goes on between scientists in all branches of Science can be made rigorously logical and, therefore, can lead us to true knowledge. They intended to apply their analytic-synthetic distinction to all statements in such a rigorous way that any statement made by anyone in any field could be judged by this standard. If the truth or falsity of a statement had to be checked by observations made in the real, material world, then it was clearly a synthetic statement. If the statement’s truth value could be assessed by careful analysis of its internal logic, without reference to observations and measurements made in the material world, then the statement was clearly an analytic statement. Idea exchanges that were limited to only these types of statements could be logically sound. All other statements were to be regarded as meaningless. 

The logical positivists argued that following these prescriptions was all that was needed to make the scientific talk that scientists engage in with each other, as they explain their research and size up the research of their fellow scientists, logically sound and so to lead scientists by gradual steps on to true, reliable knowledge of the real world. All other communications by humans were to be regarded as forms of emotional venting, empty of any real content or meaning.

               
                                                                  Rudolph Carnap 
  
  Carnap, especially, set out prove that these prescriptions were all that Science needed in order for it to work and to progress in a rigorously logical way toward making more and more accurate statements about the real world – generalizations that could be trusted as universal truths. (2.)

       
                                                    Willard V. O. Quine


 But the theories of Carnap and the other positivists were taken apart by later philosophers such as Quine, who showed that the crucial positivist distinction between analytic and synthetic statements was not logically defensible. Explaining what makes an analytic statement (e.g. “All bachelors are unmarried men”) analytic requires that we first understand what “synonymous” terms (like “bachelors” and “unmarried men”) are. But if we go into the logic carefully, we find that explaining what makes two terms “synonymous” presupposes that we first understand what “analytic” means. In short, trying to lay down precise rules for defining the difference between analytic statements and synthetic ones only leads us to reason in circles. (3.)


          
                                                    Hilary Putnam               

Quine’s reasoning, in turn, was further critiqued and refined by later philosophers like Hilary Putnam. As Putnam eventually put the matter:     

            “… positivism produced a conception of rationality so narrow as to exclude the very          activity of producing that conception.”

            “… the whole system of knowledge is justified as a whole by its utility in predicting      [future] observations.” (4.)

In other words, logical positivism’s rigid way of talking about thinking, knowing, and expressing ends up in a logically unsolvable paradox. It creates new problems for all our systems of ideas and doesn’t help with solving any of the old problems.

We can see that most of the laws that have been formulated by scientists really do work. They guide us toward ways of living that get results. Why they work and how much we can rely on them - i.e. how much we can trust Science - are a lot trickier to explain.      


No comments:

Post a Comment

What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.