Chapter 4. Part B
The moral philosophers’ hope of finding
an Empiricist foundation for a moral system was broken by thinkers like Quine and
Godel. However, Rationalism’s flaws were just as clearly shown up by psychologists
such as Aronson and Festinger.
Elliot Aronson
Aronson
was Festinger's student, who went on to win much acclaim in his own right. What
they both worked on the most was cognitive dissonance theory. Cognitive
dissonance theory says something fairly simple, but its consequences are
profound and far-reaching. Basically, it says that the inclination of our human
minds is always toward finding what sound like good reasons for doing what we
want to do anyway, and even more vigorously argued reasons for the things we've
already done. (See Aronson's "The Social Animal".) (1.)
What it says
essentially is this: a human organism tends, actively, insistently, and
insidiously, to think and act so as to perceive and affirm itself as being
consistent with itself. The mind shows in every action that it directs the body
to do, and especially in every phrase that it directs the body to utter, the
desire to remain consistent with itself. In practice, what this means is that
humans tend to find and state what appear to themselves to be good reasons for
doing what they will have to do anyway in order to maintain the conditions of
life with which they have become comfortable. The mind strives constantly
inside the individual human brain to make theory match practice or practice
match theory – or to adjust both – in order to reduce its own internal
"clashing", i.e. what psychologists call "cognitive
dissonance".
A novice financial advisor who used to speak
disparagingly of all sales jobs will soon be able to tell you with heartfelt
sincerity why every person, including you, ought to have a carefully selected
portfolio of stocks. The physician adds another bank of expensive tests and
therapies – both of doubtful effectiveness – every year or so to his
repertoire. The plastic surgeon can show with argument and evidence that all of
the cosmetic procedures he performs should be covered by the state's health
care plan because his patients aren’t spoiled and vain, they are
"aesthetically handicapped".
The divorce lawyer is not setting two people
who used to love one another at each other's throats. He is merely defending
his client's best interests, while his client's misery and despair – at the depths
of cruelty to which he and his former spouse have sunk – grow more profound
every week. The cigarette company executive not only finds what he truly
believes are flaws in the research; he smokes over two packs a day. The general
does indeed send his own son to the front. Even his mother-in-law's decent
qualities (not her rude ones) become more obvious to him on the day on which he
learns that she owns over ten million dollars worth of real estate. (All that
worry! No wonder she’s rude.)
And the Philosophy professor, whose mind is
trained to seek out inconsistencies? He once said that he believed in the
primacy of the rights of the individual over any group rights. He sought to
abolish any taxes that might be used to pay for social services. Private
charities could do such work, if it needed to be done at all. But then his
daughter, who suffers from bipolar disorder, and sometimes secretly goes off
her medications and runs away from all forms of care, no matter how loving, ran
off and became one of the homeless in the streets of a distant city. She was
spotted and saved from almost certain death by alert street workers, paid
(meagerly) by the state government. Now he argues for the responsibility of
citizens to pay taxes that can be used to create programs that hire street
workers who look out for, and look after, the destitute and unfortunate in
society.
He once considered euthanasia to be totally
immoral. But now his aging dad with Alzheimer's disease has been deteriorating
for over five years. Professor X is broke, sick, and exhausted himself. He
longs for the heart-ache to be over. He knows that he cannot keep caring
personally, day in and day out, for the needs of this now unrecognizable,
pathetic, gnarled creature for very much longer. Even Dad, the Dad he once
knew, would have agreed. Dad needs and deserves a gentle needle. Professor X is
certain of it, and he tells his grad students and colleagues so during their
quiet, confidential moments.
Do we, in our endlessly subtle rationalizations,
see what is not there? Not really. Out of the billions of sense details, the
googuls of patterns that we might see among them, and the near infinite numbers
of interpretations that we might give to those details, we tend to give
prominence in our minds to those that are consistent with the view of ourselves
and our way of life that we find psychologically most comforting. We don't like
seeing ourselves as hypocrites. We don't like living with nagging feelings of
anxiety (cognitive dissonance). Therefore, we tend to favor, and be drawn to,
ways of thinking, speaking, and acting that will reduce that dissonance,
especially in our internal pictures of ourselves. In private, inside our heads,
we need to like ourselves.
There is nothing really profound being said
so far. But when we come to applying this theory to philosophies, the
implications are a little startling.
Other than
rationalizations, the rationalists have nothing to offer.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.