Chapter 7 Bayesianism: A Major Theoretical
Criticism And A Response Part A
The Bayesian way of explaining how we think
about, test, and then adopt a new model of reality has been given a number of
mathematical formulations. They look complicated, but they really aren’t that
hard. I have chosen one of the more intuitive ones below because I intend to
use it to discuss the theoretical criticism of Bayesianism which I mentioned in
the last chapter.
The Bayesian model of how a human being’s
thinking evolves can be broken down into a few basic components. When I, as a
typical, modern human, am examining a new way of explaining what I see going on
in the world, I am considering a new hypothesis, and as I try to judge just how
true – and therefore how useful – a picture of the world this new hypothesis
may give me, I look for ways of testing the hypothesis that will tend to show
decisively one way or the other whether this new hypothesis and the model of
reality that it is based on really work. What I am trying to determine is
whether or not this hypothesis will help me to understand, anticipate, and
respond effectively to, events in my world.
When I encounter a test situation that fits
within the range of events that the hypothesis is supposed to be able to
explain and make predictions about, I tend to become more convinced that the
hypothesis is a true one if it does indeed enable me to make accurate predictions.
(And I tend to be more likely to discard the hypothesis if the predictions that
it leads me to make keep failing to be realized.) I am especially more inclined
to accept the hypothesis and the model of reality that it is based on, if it
enables me to make reliable predictions about the outcomes of these test
situations and, if also, in the meantime, all of my other theories and models
are silent or inaccurate when it comes to explaining my observations of these
same test situations.
It is worth noting again here that this same
process can also occur in a whole nation when increasing numbers of citizens
become convinced that a new way of doing things is more effective than the
status quo practices. "Popular" ideas, the few that really work,
last. In other words, both individuals and whole societies really do learn,
grow, and change by the Bayesian model.
In the case of a whole society, the clusters
of ideas that an individual sorts through and tries to shape into a larger
idea-system become clusters of citizens, forming factions within society, each
arguing for the way of thinking that it favors. The leaders of each faction
search for reasoning and evidence to support their positions in ways that are
closely analogous to the ways in which the various biases in an individual mind
struggle to become the idea system that the individual follows. The difference
is that the individual usually does not settle very heated internal debates by
blinding his right eye with his left hand. (i.e. Each of us, usually, chooses
to set aside unresolvable internal disputes rather than letting them make him
crazy. Societies, on the other hand, have riots and, sometimes, revolutions.)
In societies, factions sometimes work out
their differences, reach consensus, and move on without violence. But
sometimes, of course, as noted above, they seem to have to fight it out. Then
violence between factions within society, or violence with the neighboring
society that is perceived as being the carrier of the threatening new ideas,
settles the matter. But Bayesian calculations are always in play in the minds
of the participants, and these same calculations almost always eventually
dictate the outcome. One side gives in and learns the new ways. The most
extreme alternative, one tribe’s complete and genocidal extermination of the
other, is only rarely the final outcome.
But let us now deal with the flaw that is seen - mistakenly, I will argue - by the critics of Bayesianism in the mathematical formula that purports to model the Bayesian decision-making process.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.