Chapter 4. Part C
What are Plato's ideal "forms"? Can I
measure one? Weigh it? If I claim to know the "forms" and you claim
to know them, how might we figure out whether the "forms" you know
are the same ones that I know? If, in a perfect dimension somewhere, there is a
form of a perfect horse, what were eohippus and mesohippus, who were horsing
around long before anything Plato could have recognized as a "horse"
existed?
Similarly I have to ask: What are Descartes'
"clear and distinct ideas". “Clear and distinct” to whom? Him? His
contemporaries? They do not seem to me to be so clear and distinct that I can
base my thinking on them and thus stake my sanity and survival on them. I know
that there are many people now living and many who have lived who do not, or
did not, know what he was talking about. Not in any language. Yet they were, and
are, fully human people. Some of Descartes’ favorite “clear and distinct
ideas”, i.e. the basic ideas of arithmetic and geometry, are unknown in some human
cultures.
This evidence suggests very strongly to me that Descartes'
categories are simply not that "clear and distinct". If they were
inherent in all human minds, all humans would develop these ideas as they
matured, a point first noted by Locke. Looking at a lot of humans, especially
ones in other cultures, tells us that Descartes’ clear and distinct ideas are
not built in. We acquire them by learning them. To me, arguing that they are
somehow real, and that, in the meantime sensory experience is illusory, is a
way of thinking that can then be extended to arguing for the realness of the
creations of fantasy writers. In "The Hobbit", Tolkien describes ents
and orcs, and I go along with the fantasy for as long as it amuses me, but
there are no ents, however much I may enjoy imagining them.
J.R.R. Tolkien
On
the contrary, all concepts are merely mental models that help us to organize
our memories in useful ways, ways that make it easier for us to plan and then act.
Even ideas of numbers, Descartes' favorite “clear” ideas, are merely mental
tools that are more useful than “ents”. Counting things helps us to act strategically
in the material world and thus to survive. Imagining ents gives us temporary
amusement - not a bad thing, though not nearly as useful as an understanding of
numbers.
But numbers,
like ents, are mental constructs. In reality, there are never two of anything.
No two people are exactly alike, nor are two trees, two rocks, two rivers, or
two stars. Then what are we actually counting? We are counting clumps of mental data that approximate concepts built up from memories of experiences. Concepts
far more useful in the survival game than the concept of an ent. And even those
concepts that seem to be built into us (e.g. basic language concepts) became "built
in" ones because over generations of evolution of the human genome, those
concepts (e.g. noun, verb) gave a survival advantage to their carriers. Language enables improved
teamwork; teamwork works. Thus, as a physically explainable phenomenon, the
human capacity for language also comes back into the fold of empiricism.
Geneticists can
locate the genes that enable a developing embryo to build a language center in
the future child's brain. Later, perhaps, MRI scanning can find the place in
your brain where your language program is located. If you have a tumor there, a
neuro-surgeon may fix the "hardware" so that a speech therapist can
then help you to fix the program. The human capacity for language is an
empirical phenomenon all the way down. (2.)
In the meantime, counting enabled more effective
hunter-gatherer behavior. If the leader of the tribe knew that he had seen
eight of the things his tribe call "deer" go into an area of bush,
and if only seven had come out, he could calculate that if his friends caught
up and circled around in time, and if they could execute well, work as a team,
and kill, this week the children would not starve. Both the ability to count
things, and the ability to articulate detailed instructions, boosted a
primitive tribe’s odds of surviving.
Thus were the rudiments of arithmetic and
language built up in us. And if the pre-cursors of language seem to be
genetically built-in (human toddlers all over the world grasp that nouns are different
from verbs), while the precursors of math are not, this fact would only
indicate that basic language concepts proved far more valuable in the survival
game than basic math ones. (Really useful concepts, like the concepts of
heights or snakes, get written into the genotype.) The innate nature of
language skills would not indicate that either basic language concepts or basic
arithmetic concepts are coming to us by some mysterious, inexplicable process
out of the ideal dimension of the pure Good.
We do not have to believe – as the
Rationalists say we do – in another dimension of pure thought, with herds of
“forms” or “distinct ideas” roaming its plains, in order to have confidence in
our own ability to reason. By nature or by nurture, or subtle combinations of
the two, we acquire and pass on to our kids those concepts that enable their carriers
to survive. In short, Reason’s roots can be explained in ways that don’t assume
any of the things that Rationalism assumes.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.