Chapter 3. Part E
Now the problems described so far bother philosophers of
Science a great deal, but such problems are of little or no interest to the
majority of scientists. They see the law-like statements that they and their
colleagues try to formulate as being testable in only one meaningful way,
namely by the results shown in experiments done in the lab or in the field.
Thus, when scientists want to talk about what knowing is, they look for models
not in Philosophy, but in the branches of Science that study human thinking.
However, efforts to provide material proof of Empiricism, e.g. in neurology,
also run into problems.
In his writings, the early Empiricist, John
Locke, basically dodged the problem when he defined the human mind as a “blank
slate” and saw its abilities to perceive and reason as being due to its two
“fountains of knowledge”, Sensation and Reflection. The first, he says, is made
up of stores of sensory experiences and memories of sensory experiences. The
second is made up of the “ideas …the mind gets by reflecting on its own
operations within itself”. How these “operations” got into human consciousness
and what it is that is doing the “reflecting” on these “operations” he doesn’t
say. (5.)
Modern empiricists, both philosophers of Science and scientists
themselves, don't care for their forbears giving in to this kind of
mystery-making. Scientists, especially, aim to figure out what the mind is and
how it thinks by studying not words but physical things, things such as the
human genome, and what it makes, namely, among its many other creations, the
neurons of the brain. That is the modern empiricist way, the scientific way.
For today's scientists, talk about what
knowing is, no matter how clever the talk, is not getting us any closer to
understanding what knowing is. In fact, scientists don't respect talk about
anything that we may want to study unless that talk is backed up with
scientific theories or models of the thing being studied, and the theories are
further backed up with research done on real things in the real world.
Scientific research, to qualify as
scientific, also must be designed so that it can be replicated by any
researcher in any land or era. Otherwise, it’s not credible; it could be a
coincidence, a mistake, wishful thinking, or simply a lie. Thus, for modern
scientists, the analysis of material evidence offers the only route by which a
researcher can come to understand anything, even in this case in which the
thing that she is studying is what is happening inside of her as she is
studying.
She sees a phenomenon in reality, gets an
idea about how it works, designs an experiment, tests her theory, then records
the results and interprets them. The aim of the statements she then makes is to
guide future research onto more and more fruitful paths and to build
technologies that are more and more effective at predicting and/or manipulating
events in the real world. Electro-chemical pathways among the neurons of the
brain, for example – individual paths and whole patterns of such paths – can be
studied in labs and correlated with subjects’ own reported perceptions. (The state of
research in this field is described by Delany in a 2011 article available
online and also in several articles, notably Revonsuo’s, in a book edited in
2000 by Metzinger, also available online.) (6.) (7.)
Material things that can be observed and measured by all are the things that Science
cares about. The philosophers’ talk about what thinking and knowing are is just
talk.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.