Chapter 6 – The First Attack on
Bayesianism and How It Can Be Answered
(credit: Public Domain Pictures)
The
idea behind Bayesianism is straightforward enough to be grasped by nearly all
adults in any land. But the idea of radical Bayesianism escapes us. The radical
form of Bayesianism says all we do, mentally, fits inside the Bayesian model. But
it is very human to dread such a view of ourselves and to slip into thinking that
radical Bayesianism must be wrong. We want desperately to believe at least a
few of our core ideas are unshakable. Too often, unfortunately, people think
they have found one. But to a true Bayesian, the one truth that he believes is probably
absolute is the one that says there are no absolute truths.
An
idea is a mental tool that enables you to sort and respond to sensory
experiences—single ones or whole categories of them. When you find an idea that
enables quick, accurate sorting, you keep it. What can confuse and confound
this whole picture is the way that, in the case of some of your most deeply held,
deeply programmed ideas, you didn’t personally find them. They came in a trial-and-error
way to some of your ancestors, who found the ideas so useful that they then did
their best to program these ideas into their children, and thus they were
passed down the generations to your parents and then to you.
Every
idea you acquire is installed as part of your mental equipment, after careful
Bayesian calculations, either by the process of your own noticing, considering,
and testing it, or by your family and your tribe programming you with the idea
because the tribe’s early leaders acquired this idea by the first process.
Consciousness and even sanity are constantly evolving for all humans, all the
time. We keep rewriting our concept sets, from complex ideas like justice and love to basic ideas like up
and down and even to what I mean by I. (Individual minds can indeed be made
to reprogram their notions of up and down.1) Your barest you is a dynamic, self-referencing
system that is constantly checking its sense perceptions against its models/ideas
about what reality should be and then updating and rewriting itself.
A
short side note is in order here. A few commonly used, species-wide ideas, or
proto-ideas, are not acquired by either of the above methods because these
ideas are hardwired into us at birth. These are not programmed into humans by our
tribe nor by our own life experiences so they don’t fit into either of the
categories just described. But they do fit inside the modern empiricist view of
what knowledge is simply because in that view, with the models it has gained
from the biological sciences, especially genetics, these built-in ideas are
seen as genetically-acquired anatomical traits and thus as subjects for study
by geneticists or neurophysiologists. In short, scientists can go looking for
them directly in the human brain, and they do.
For
example, some basic ideas of language are built into all normal humans, but the
genes that cause the fetus to build the language center in its developing
brain are still being identified. In addition, the structures and functions of
these brain areas, once they’re built, are only poorly understood. In our
present discussion, however, these issues can be passed by. They are biological
rather than philosophical in nature and thus outside our present scope. These
genes and the brain structures that are built from the gene-coded information
might someday be manipulated, by behavior modification, genetic engineering,
surgery, drugs, or other technologies we cannot now imagine.
But
whether such actions will be judged right or wrong and whether they will be
permitted in the normal institutions of our society will depend on our moral
values.
These, as we have already seen, are going to need something more at
their core than what is offered by empiricism. Empiricism, as its own moral
guide, has proved neither sound in theory nor effective in practice. The
evidence of human history strongly suggests that Science, at least so far, has
failed at being its own moral guide. This line of thought returns us to our philosophical
discussion of moralities and their sources—and so back to Bayesianism.
This
Bayesian model of how we think is so radical that at first it eludes us. To
each individual, the idea that she is continually adjusting her entire mindset,
and that no parts of it, not even her deepest ideas of who she is or what
reality is, can ever be fully trusted is disturbing to say the least. Doubting
our most basic ideas is flirting on the edge of mental illness. Even
considering the possibility is upsetting. But this radical Bayesian view is certainly
the one I arrive at when I look back honestly over the changes I have undergone
in my own life. The Bayesian model of how a “self” is formed, and how it
evolves as the organism ages, fits the set of memories that I call “myself”
exactly.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.