There
is nothing really profound being stated in my last few posts. But when we come to applying
this theory to philosophies, the implications are a little startling.
Other
than rationalizations, the rationalists have nothing to offer.
What
are Plato’s ideal “forms”? Can I measure one? Weigh it? If I claim to know the
forms and you claim to know them, how might we figure out whether the forms you
know are the same ones I know? If, in a perfect dimension somewhere, there is a
form of a perfect horse, what were creatures called eohippus and mesohippus
(biological ancestors of the horse), who were horsing around long before
anything Plato could have recognized as a horse existed?
Similarly,
we can ask: What are Descartes’s “clear and distinct ideas?” Clear and distinct
to whom? Him? His contemporaries? To me, they do not seem so clear and distinct
that I can base my thinking on them and thus stake my sanity and survival on
them. Many people have not known what he was talking about. Not in any
language. Yet they were, and are, fully human people. Some of Descartes’s favorite
clear and distinct ideas—the basic ideas of arithmetic and geometry—are unknown
in some human cultures.
This
evidence suggests strongly that Descartes’ categories are simply not that clear
and distinct. If they were inherent in all human minds, all humans would
develop these ideas as they matured, a point first noted by Locke. Looking at a
broad spectrum of humans, especially those in other cultures, tells us that
Descartes’s clear and distinct ideas are not built in. We acquire them by
learning them. Arguing that they are somehow real, and that in the meantime
sensory experience is illusory, is a way of thinking that can then be extended
to arguing for the realness of the creations of fantasy writers. In The Hobbit, Tolkien describes Ents and Orcs,
and I go along with the fantasy for as long as it amuses me, but there are no Ents,
however much I may enjoy imagining them.
J.R.R. Tolkien (credit: Wikipedia)
On
the contrary, all concepts are merely mental models that help us to organize
our memories in useful ways that make it easier for us to plan and then act.
Even ideas of numbers, Descartes’s favourite “clear” ideas, are merely mental
tools that are more useful than Ents. Counting things helps us to act strategically
in the material world and thus to survive. Imagining Ents gives us temporary
amusement—not a bad thing, though not nearly as useful as an understanding of
numbers.
But
numbers, like Ents, are mental constructs. In reality, there are never two of
anything. No two people are exactly alike, nor are two trees, two rocks, two
rivers, or two stars. So what are we actually counting? We are counting clumps
of sense data that approximate concepts built up from memories of experiences,
concepts far more useful in the survival game than the concept of an Ent. And
even those concepts that seem to be built into us (e.g., basic language
concepts) became built-in because, over generations of evolution of the human
genome, those concepts gave a survival advantage to their carriers. Language
enables improved teamwork; teamwork works. Thus, as an empiriically explainable
phenomenon, the human capacity for language also comes back into the fold of
empiricism.
Geneticists
can locate the genes that enable a developing embryo to build a language centre
in the future child’s brain. Later, MRI scanning can find the place in
your brain where your language program is located. If you have a tumour there,
a neurosurgeon may fix the “hardware” so that a speech therapist can help you
to fix the program. The human capacity for language is an empirical phenomenon
all the way down.2
In
the meantime, counting enabled more effective hunter-gatherer behavior. If a
tribe leader saw eight of the things his tribe called deer go into the bush and if only seven came out, he could
calculate that if his friends caught up, circled around in time, and executed
well, if they worked as a team and killed, this week the children would not
starve. Both the ability to count things and the ability to articulate detailed
instructions to the rest of one’s tribe boosted a primitive tribe’s odds of
surviving.
Thus
were the rudiments of arithmetic and language built up in us. And if the
precursors of language seem to be genetically built in—for example, human
toddlers all over the world grasp that nouns are different from verbs—while the
precursors of math are not, this fact would only indicate that basic language concepts
proved far more valuable in the survival game than basic math ones. (Really
useful concepts, like our wariness of heights or snakes, get written into the
genotype.) The innate nature of language skills would indicate that neither
basic language concepts nor basic arithmetic concepts are coming to us by some
mysterious, inexplicable process out of Plato’s ideal dimension of the pure
Good.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.