We
can see that most of the laws that have been formulated by scientists do work.
They guide us toward ways of living that get results. Why they work and how
much we can rely on them—i.e. how much we can trust Science—are a lot trickier
to explain.
Now,
while the problems described so far bother philosophers of science a
great deal, such problems are of little or no interest to the majority of
scientists themselves. They see the law-like statements that they and their
colleagues try to formulate as being testable in only one meaningful way;
namely, by the results shown in replicable experiments done in the lab or in
the field. Thus, when scientists want to talk about what knowing is, they look
for models not in Philosophy, but in the branches of Science that study human
thinking. However, efforts to find proof of empiricism in neurology, for
example, also run into problems.
In
his writings, the early empiricist John Locke basically dodged the problem when
he defined the human mind as a “blank slate” and saw its abilities to perceive
and reason as being due to its two “fountains of knowledge,” sensation and reflection. Sensation, he said, is made up of current sensory experiences and of memories of
past experiences. Reflection is made up of the “ideas … the mind gets by
reflecting on its own operations within itself.” How these kinds of operations
got into human consciousness and what is doing the reflecting that he is describing, he doesn’t say.5
Modern
empiricists, both philosophers of Science and scientists themselves, don’t care
for their forebears giving in to this kind of mystery-making. Scientists aim to figure out what the mind is and how it thinks by studying not
words but physical things such as the human genome and what it creates, namely—among
its many other creations—the neurons of the brain. That is the modern
empiricist way, the scientific way.
For
today’s scientists, discussions about what knowing is, no matter how clever, are
not bringing us any closer to understanding what knowing is. In fact, typically
scientists don’t respect discussions about anything we may want to study unless
they are backed with theories or models of the thing being studied, and the
theories are further backed with research conducted on real things in the real
world.
Scientific
research, to qualify as scientific, must also be designed so it can be
replicated by any researcher in any land or era. Otherwise, it’s not credible;
it could be a mistake, a coincidence, wishful thinking, or simply a lie. Thus,
for modern scientists, the analysis of material evidence offers the only route
by which a researcher can come to understand anything, even when the thing she
is studying is what’s happening inside her as she is doing her studying.
She
sees a phenomenon in reality, gets an idea about how it works and designs an
experiment. She tests her theory, then records the results and interprets them. The
aim of her statements about what she finds is to guide future research onto more fruitful paths and
to figure out how to build technologies that are effective at predicting and
manipulating events in the real world.
Electro-chemical pathways among the
neurons of the brain, for example, can be studied in labs and correlated with subjects’ perceptions and actions. (The
state of research in this field is described by Donelson Delany in a 2011
article available online and in several other articles, notably Antti Revonsuo’s
in Neural Correlates of Consciousness:
Empirical and Conceptual Questions, edited by Thomas Metzinger.6,7)
Observable
things are the things Science cares about. The philosophers’ talk about what
thinking and knowing are is just that—talk.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.