Eohippus (artist's conception)
(By Heinrich Harder [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons)
Do we, in our endlessly subtle rationalizations, see
what is not there? Not really. A fairer way of describing this dissonnance-reducing tendency in human minds is to say that out of the billions of sense details, the
googols of patterns we might see among them, and the infinite interpretations
we might give to those details, we tend to give prominence to those that are
consistent with the view of ourselves that we find most psychologically comforting. We don’t like seeing ourselves as hypocrites. We don’t like nagging
feelings of cognitive dissonance. Therefore, we tend to be drawn to ways of thinking,
speaking, and acting that reduce that dissonance, especially in our internal
pictures of ourselves. In short, inside our heads, we need to like ourselves.
There
is nothing really profound being stated so far. But when we come to applying
this theory to philosophies, the implications are a little startling.
Other than rationalizations, the rationalists have
nothing to offer.
What are Plato’s ideal “forms”? Can I measure one?
Weigh it? If I claim to know the forms and you claim to know them, how might we
figure out whether the forms you know are the same ones I know? If, in a
perfect dimension somewhere, there is a form of a perfect horse, what were creatures
called eohippus and mesohippus (biological ancestors of the horse), who were
horsing around long before anything Plato could have recognized as a horse
existed?
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.