We can see that most of the laws that have been formulated
by scientists do work. They guide us toward ways of living that get results.
Why they work and how much we can rely on them—i.e. how much we can trust Science—are
a lot trickier to explain.
Now, while the problems described so far bother philosophers
of Science a great deal, such problems are of little or no interest to the
majority of scientists themselves. They see the law-like statements that they
and their colleagues try to formulate as being testable in only one meaningful
way, namely, by the results shown in replicable experiments done in the lab or
in the field. Thus, when scientists want to talk about what knowing is, they
look for models not in Philosophy, but in the branches of Science that study
human thinking. However, efforts to find proof of empiricism in neurology, for
example, also run into problems.
In his writings, the early empiricist John Locke
basically dodged the problem when he defined the human mind as a “blank slate”
and saw its abilities to perceive and reason as being due to its two “fountains
of knowledge,” sensation and reflection. Sensation, he said, is made up of current
sensory experiences and memories of past experiences. Reflection is made up of
the “ideas … the mind gets by reflecting on its own operations within itself.”
How these kinds of operations got into human consciousness and what is doing
the “reflecting” that he is talking about, he doesn’t say.5
Modern empiricists, both philosophers of Science
and scientists themselves, don’t care for their forebears giving in to this
kind of mystery-making. Scientists aim to figure out what the mind is and how
it thinks by studying not words but physical things such as the human genome
and what it creates, namely the neurons of the brain. That is the modern
empiricist way, the scientific way.
For today’s scientists, discussions about what
knowing is, no matter how clever, are not bringing us any closer to
understanding what knowing is. In fact, typically scientists don’t respect discussions
about anything we may want to study unless they are backed with theories or
models of the thing being studied, and the theories are further backed with
research conducted on real things in the real world.
Scientific research, to qualify as scientific, must
also be designed so it can be replicated by any researcher in any land or era.
Otherwise, it’s not credible; it could be a coincidence, a mistake, wishful
thinking, or simply a lie. Thus, for modern scientists, the analysis of
material evidence offers the only route by which a researcher can come to
understand anything, even when the thing she is studying is what’s happening
inside her as she studies.
She sees a phenomenon in reality, gets an idea
about how it works, then designs an experiment. She tests her theory, then
records the results and interprets them. The aim of her statements is to guide
future research onto more fruitful paths and to build technologies that are increasingly
effective at predicting and manipulating events in the real world.
Electro-chemical pathways among the neurons of the brain, for example can be
studied in labs and correlated with subjects’ perceptions and actions. (The
state of research in this field is described by Donelson Delany in a 2011
article available online and in several other articles, notably Antti Revonsuo’s
in Neural Correlates of Consciousness:
Empirical and Conceptual Questions, edited by Thomas Metzinger.6,7)
Observable things are the things Science cares
about. The philosophers’ talk about what thinking and knowing are is just that—talk.
university lecture during the 1300's (credit: Wikipedia)
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.