Various further attempts have been made in the last
hundred years to nail down what scientific thinking does and to prove that it
is a reliable way to truth, but they have all come with conundrums of their
own.
The logical positivists, for example, tried to
bypass Hume’s problems with the terms in scientific laws and to place the
burden of meaning and proof onto whole propositions instead. A key point in the
logical positivists’ case is that all meaningful statements are either analytic
or synthetic. Any statement that does not fit into one of these two categories,
the positivists say, is irrelevant noise.
Analytic statements are those whose truth or
falsity is determined by the definitions of the terms they contain. For
example, “All bachelors are unmarried men” is an analytic statement. If we
understand the terms in the sentence we can immediately verify, by thinking it
through, whether the statement is true.
Synthetic statements are those whose truth or
falsity we must work out by referring to evidence found in the real, empirical
world, not in the statement itself. “All substances contract when cooled” is a
synthetic statement—not quite a true one, as observations of water and ice can
show. So is “If a creature is a whale, then it is a mammal.”
The logical positivists aimed to show that discussions
between scientists in all disciplines can be made rigorously logical and can therefore
lead us to true knowledge. They intended to apply their analytic–synthetic
distinction to all statements in such a rigorous way that any statement made by
anyone in any field could be judged by this standard. If the truth or falsity
of a statement had to be checked by observations made in the real, material
world, then it was clearly a synthetic statement. If the statement’s truth
value could be assessed by careful analysis of its internal logic, without
reference to observations and measurements made in the material world, then the
statement was clearly an analytic statement. Idea exchanges that were limited
to only these types of statements could be logically sound. All other
statements were to be regarded as meaningless.
The logical positivists argued that following these
prescriptions was all that was needed for scientists to engage in logically
sound discussions, explain their research, and size up the research of their
fellow scientists. This would lead them by gradual steps on to true, reliable
knowledge of the real world. All other communications by humans were to be
regarded as forms of emotional venting, empty of any real content or meaning.
Rudolf Carnap, especially, set out prove that these
prescriptions were all that science needed in order for it to work and to
progress in a rigorously logical way toward making increasingly accurate
statements about the real world—generalizations that could be trusted as
universal truths.2
But the theories of Carnap and the other positivists
were taken apart by later philosophers such as Willard Quine, who showed that
the crucial positivist distinction between analytic and synthetic statements
was not logically defensible. Explaining what makes an analytic statement (e.g.,
“All bachelors are unmarried men”) analytic requires that we first understand
what synonymous terms like bachelors
and unmarried men are. But if we go
into the logic carefully, we find that explaining what makes two terms
synonymous presupposes that we first understand what analytic means. In short, trying to lay down precise rules for
defining the difference between analytic statements and synthetic ones only leads
us to reason in circles.3
Hilary Putnam (credit:
Wikimedia Commons)
Quine’s reasoning, in turn, was further critiqued
and refined by later philosophers like Hilary Putnam. As Putnam eventually put
the matter:
“… positivism produced a conception of rationality
so narrow as to exclude the very activity of producing that conception” and “…
the whole system of knowledge is justified as a whole by its utility in
predicting [future] observations.”4
In other words, logical positivism’s rigid way of
talking about thinking, knowing, and expressing ends up in a logically
unsolvable paradox. It creates new problems for all our systems of ideas and
doesn’t help with solving any of the old problems. In the end, the empiricist, scientific system of
knowledge gets its credibility with us because it, mostly, gets results. It enables
us to predict and control some of what’s coming in reality.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.