Chapter
7 Bayesianism:
How It Works
Thomas
Bayes (credit: Wikimedia Commons)
The best answer to the problem of what human minds and human knowing are is that, in reality, we are all Bayesians. On Bayesianism, I can build a universal moral system.
So, what is Bayesianism?
Thomas Bayes was a
Presbyterian minister, statistician, and philosopher who formulated the theorem
named for him: Bayes’ Theorem. His theory of how humans form
tentative beliefs and gradually turn those beliefs into concepts has been given
several mathematical formulations, but it says a fairly simple thing.
Bayes’ Theorem says this: we tend to
become more convinced of the truth of a theory or model of reality the more we
keep encountering bits of evidence that, first, support the theory and, second,
can’t be explained by any of the competing theories our minds already hold. (An
accessible explanation of Bayes’ Theorem is on the Cornell University Math
Department website.1)
Under the Bayesian model, we never
claim to know anything for certain. Empiricism and Rationalism both aim to
provide us with a way of thinking that can lead us to unshakable truths. But
Bayesianism does not claim to seek perfect truth. Instead, it says that we hold
most firmly a few beliefs we consider highly probable, and we use them as we
make decisions in our lives. We then assign lesser degrees of probability to
our more peripheral beliefs, and we constantly track the evidence confirming or
disconfirming our beliefs. Under Bayesianism, we accept that all beliefs, at
every level of generality, need constant updating, even the ones that have been
working well at guiding us to handle real life. It is far more akin to
Empiricism than Rationalism, but beyond both. Agile. Alive.
For most people, in their daily lives,
the more a theory enables them to establish some kind of overall order that
covers all their concepts and memories, the more persuasive the theory seems.
If the evidence favoring the theory mounts, and its degree of consistency with
the rest of the concepts and memories in the mind also grows, then finally, in
a leap of understanding, the mind promotes the theory up to the status of a
belief and incorporates the new belief into its total stock of thinking
machinery. Once I understand how evolution works, I see it in every living
thing I pass. The same is true of gravity, respiration, etc..
At the same time, the mind nearly
always has to demote to inactive status some formerly held concepts that are
not commensurable with the new belief. This is especially true of all mental
activities involved in the kinds of thinking that are now being covered by the
new theory. For example, once you absorb and accept a theory of how your immune
system works, that concept will inform every health-related decision you make
thereafter – diet, vitamins, exercise, etc.
In life, examples of the workings of
Bayesianism can be seen all the time. All we need do is look closely at how we
and the people around us make up our minds.
When I was in junior high school, each
year in June, I and all the other students of the school were bussed to the
city track meet at a stadium in West Edmonton. Student athletes from all the
major junior high schools in the city came to compete in the biggest track meet
of the year. Its being held near the end of the school year, of course, added
to the excitement of the day.
A few of the athletes competing came
from a special school that educated and cared for those kids who today would be
called “mentally challenged”. In my Grade 9 year, three of my friends and I, on
a patch of grass beside the bleachers, did a mock cheer in which we shouted the
name of this school in a short rhyming chant, attempted some clumsy dance kicks
in step, crashed into each other, and fell down – all in an obviously mocking
style. I should make clear that I did not learn such a cruel attitude from my
home. Had they seen this stunt, my parents would have been furious. But
fourteen-year-olds with their peers can be cruel.
The problem was that one of the
prettiest, smartest girls in my Grade 9 class, Ann, was sitting in the
bleachers, watching field events in a lull between track events. She and two of
her friends happened to catch our little routine. By the glares on their faces,
I could see they were not amused. Later that day, I learned that she had an
older brother who had attended our school and earned excellent marks, but she
also had a younger brother who had Down syndrome.
I apologized lamely the next day at
school, but it was clear I’d lost all chance with her. However, she said one
thing that stayed with me. She told me that if you form a bond with a mentally
retarded person (retarded was the word we used in those days), you
will soon realize you have made a friend whose loyalty, once won, is unchanging
and unshakeable – probably, the most loyal friend you will ever have. And that
realization will change you.
The idea she was expressing took root.
Then, over the next twenty years, it grew into a concept and finally into an
absolute conviction.
Francis
Galton, originator of eugenics (credit: Wikimedia Commons)
It was the proverbial thin edge of the wedge.
Earlier, I had absorbed some of the ideas of the pseudo-science called Eugenics from
one of my friends at school. I’d concluded the mentally challenged added
nothing of value to a community, but inevitably took a great deal out of it.
They could, and should, be bred out of the human genome. What Ann said made me
question those assumptions.
Over years of seeing movies like A
Child Is Waiting and Charlie, and of being exposed to
awareness-raising campaigns by families of the mentally challenged, I began to
see them in a different light. Over decades of changes in attitudes, they were
called mentally handicapped and then mentally
challenged or special needs, and the changing terminology
did matter. It changed society’s thinking.
I became a teacher, and then, in the
middle of my career, mentally challenged kids began to be integrated into the
public school where I taught. I saw with increasing clarity what they could
teach the rest of us, just by being themselves.
Tracy was severely handicapped,
mentally and physically. Trish, on the other hand, was a reasonably bright girl
who had rage issues. She beat up other girls, she stole, she skipped class, she
smoked pot behind the school. But when Tracy came to us, Trish proved in a few
weeks to be the best with Tracy of any of the students in the school. Her
attentiveness and gentleness were humbling to see. In Tracy, Trish found
someone who needed her; it changed everything for Trish. As I watched them
together one day, it changed me. Years of persuasion and experience, by gradual
degrees, finally, got to me. I saw a new order in the community in which I
lived, a new view of inclusiveness that gave coherence to years of memories. We
are all siblings caring for each other.
Today, I believe the mentally
challenged are people. But it was only grudgingly at fourteen that I began to
re-examine my beliefs about them. At fourteen, I liked believing my mind was
made up on every issue. Only years of gradually growing awareness led me to
change my view. A new thinking model, gradually, by accumulation of evidence,
came to look more correct and useful to me than the old model. Then, in a kind
of conversion experience, I switched models. Of course, by gradual degrees,
through exposure to reasonable arguments and real experiences, I and a lot of
other people have come a long way on the mentally challenged from what we
believed in 1964. Humans can change. By Bayesian kinds of steps, I learned a
new way of looking at the mentally challenged.
Doberman
Pinscher (credit: Wikimedia Commons)
In a more scientific example of
Bayesianism working in my own thinking, I will also mention our Doberman
Pinscher–cross pup. Rex was basically a good dog, but he was a mutt, a Doberman
cross we acquired because one of my aunts couldn’t keep him. People often
remarked that he looked like a Doberman, but his tail was not docked. This got
me curious. I learned that most Dobermans had had their tails bobbed for many
generations, and I wondered why the tails, after many generations of docking,
had not simply become shortened at birth. I asked a Biology teacher at my high
school, but his answer only confused me. Actually, I don’t think he understood
the key concepts in Darwinian Evolution Theory himself.
Jean-Batiste Lamarck (credit:
Wikimedia Commons)
Once I got to university, I took several Biology courses. Gradually at first, and then in a breakthrough of understanding, I came to realize that I had been thinking in terms of the model of evolution called Lamarckism. At first, I did not want to let go of this cherished opinion of mine. I had always thought of myself as progressive, modern, scientific; I did not believe in Creationism. I thought I knew how evolution worked. I thought I was using an understanding of it in all my thinking. It was only after I had read more and seen by experience that docking dogs’ tails did not cause their pups’ tails to be any shorter that I came to a full understanding of Darwinian evolution.
Evolution for all species proceeds by
the combined processes of genetic variation and natural selection. It doesn’t
matter how often the anatomies of already existing members of a species are
altered if their gene pool doesn’t change. If the species’ gene pool doesn’t
change, then the next generation will, at birth, basically look pretty much
like their parents did at birth. Chopping off a dog’s tail doesn’t
change the tail genes it carries in its sperm or egg cells.
Under Lamarckism, by contrast, an
animal’s genes are pictured as changing because the animal’s body has been
stressed in some way. Lamarckism says a chimp, for instance, will pass genes
for larger arm muscles on to its young if the parent chimp is forced to use its
arm muscles a lot.
But Darwinian evolution gives us what
we now see as a far more useful picture. For example, in nature, individuals
within a species that are no longer well camouflaged in the changing flora of
their environment become easy prey for predators and so they never survive long
enough to have babies of their own. Or ones that are unable to adapt to a
cooling climate die young or reproduce less efficiently, while their
thicker-coated, or smarter, or better camouflaged cousins flourish.
Then, over generations, the gene pool
of the local community of that species does change. It contains more genes for
short, climbing legs or long, running legs or short tails or long tails or
whatever the local environment is now paying a premium for. Gradually, the
anatomy of the average species member changes. If short-tailed members have
been surviving better for the last sixty generations and long-tailed members
have been dying young, before they could reproduce, the gene pool changes.
Eventually, there will be many more individuals with short tails, a now-normal,
genetically transmitted trait of the species.
Pondering Rex’s case helped me to
absorb Darwinism. My understanding grew and then, one day, through a mental
leap, I suddenly “got” the newer, better model. A model I hadn’t understood
became clear, and it gave deeper coherence to all my ideas about living things.
Lamarckism became just an interesting footnote in the history of Science for
me, occasionally still useful because it showed me one way in which my
thinking, and that of others, could go wrong.
The question that now arises is this:
how would the Bayesian way of choosing between the Lamarckian and Darwinian
models of evolution or of reshaping one’s views on the mentally challenged
compare with the Empiricist way or the Rationalist way of dealing with these
same problems?
The chief danger of Empiricism that
Bayesians try to avoid is the insidious slip into dogmatism. In the history of
Science, many Empiricist-minded scientists have worked out and checked a theory
so thoroughly that they have slipped into thinking they have found an
unshakeable truth. For example, physicists in the late 1800s were in general
agreement that there was little left to do in Physics. Physics, for these
people, was complete. Newton and Maxwell, between them, had articulated all the
truths of the physical world, from the atomic to the cosmic. Then, Einstein’s
Theory of Relativity overthrew the Old Physics.
James
Clerk Maxwell (credit: Wikimedia Commons)
Today, Physics is in a constant state
of upheaval. A few physicists still show a longing for certainty, but most
modern physicists are tentative and cautious. They’ve been let down so many
times in the last hundred years by theories that once had seemed so promising,
but that later were shown by experiment to be flawed, that they have become
permanently wary of all “truth” claims.
It is regrettable that a similar
caution has not got into more of the physicists’ fellow scientists, especially
the biologists. Darwinism explains all aspects of the living world that we
currently know about. But it is still only a theory; it should be viewed as
tentative, and very likely, but not final or irrevocable.
The larger point for our purposes here,
however, is that while Empiricism may present the Theory of Evolution to us as
final, Bayesians never endorse any one model as the last word on anything, and
they never throw out any of the old models or theories entirely. Even those
that are clearly proven wrong have things to teach us, and of the ones that are
currently working well, we have to say, simply, that …they are currently
working well.
In contrast to Empiricism, Rationalism
has other problems, especially with the whole Theory of Evolution and what was
going on with my dog, Rex.
For Plato, the whole idea of a canine
genetic code that contained the instructions for the making of an ideal dog
would have sounded appealing. Obviously, the code must have come from the
dimension of the forms, the pure Good.
But Plato would have rejected the idea
that back a few geological ages ago no dogs existed, while some other animals
did exist that looked like dogs, but were not imperfect copies of an ideal dog
“form.” We know now these creatures can be more fruitfully thought of as
excellent examples of canis lupus variabilis, another species entirely. All
dogs, for Plato, should be seen as poor copies of the ideal dog that exists in
the pure dimension of the Good. But the fossil records in the rocks don’t so
much cast doubt on Plato’s idealism as belie it altogether. With regard to
gradual, incremental change in all species, Plato’s commitment to “forms” would
have led him to totally reject Darwin’s Theory of Evolution.
In the meantime, Descartes’s version of
Rationalism would have had serious difficulties with the mentally challenged.
Do they have minds/souls or not? If they don’t get Math and Geometry and they
can’t discuss “clear and distinct” ideas, are they human or are they mere
animals? The abilities of the mentally challenged range from slightly below
normal to severely mentally handicapped. At what point on this continuum do we
cross the threshold between human and animal? Between the realm of the soul and
that of mere matter, in other words?
Descartes’s ideas about what properties
make a human being human are disturbing. But his ideas about how we can treat
other creatures are revolting.
To Descartes, animals didn’t have
souls; therefore, humans could do whatever they wished to them and not violate
any of his moral beliefs. In his own scientific work, he dissected dogs alive.
Their screams weren’t evidence of real pain, he claimed. They had no souls and
thus could not feel pain. The noise was like the ringing of an alarm clock – a
mechanical sound, nothing more. Generations of scientists after him performed
similar acts: vivisection in the name of Science.2
Would Descartes have stuck to his
definition of what makes a being morally considerable if he had known then what
we know now about the physiology of pain? Would Plato have kept preaching his
form of Rationalism if he had been given access to the fossil records we have?
These are imponderable questions. It’s hard to imagine either of them would
have been that stubborn. But the point is that they didn’t know then what we
know now.
In any case, after considering some
likely Rationalist responses to the test situations described in this chapter,
it is certainly reasonable for us to say again that Rationalism’s way of
portraying what human minds do when they think and know is simply mistaken.
And now, we can put aside for good our
regrets about both Rationalism and Empiricism and the inadequacies of their
ways of looking at the world. We can go on to a more detailed and comprehensive
discussion of Bayesianism.
Notes
1. Bayes’ Formula, Cornell University
website, Department of Mathematics. Accessed April 6, 2015.
http://www.math.cornell.edu/~mec/2008-2009/ TianyiZheng/Bayes.html.
2. Richard Dawkins, “Richard Dawkins on
Vivisection: ‘But Can They Suffer?’” BoingBoing blog, June 30,
2011.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.