Chapter
8 How
Pervasive is Bayesianism?
Girls
Learning Sign Language, a code for communicating
(credit: David
Fulmer via Wikimedia Commons)
The idea behind Bayesianism is straightforward enough to be grasped by nearly all adults in all lands. But radical Bayesianism escapes us. The radical form of Bayesianism says all we do fits inside the Bayesian model. But it is very human to dread such a view of ourselves and then to slip into thinking Bayesianism must be wrong. We want desperately to believe that at least a few of our ideas are unshakable. Too often, unfortunately, people think they have found such an idea. But a true Bayesian knows that probably the only absolute truth is the one that says there are no absolute truths. In reality, even though we suspect that our familiar ideas and beliefs are not perfectly certain, we still use them to interpret, reason, and act in the world. Why? Because we have to. We have to move through the day. We can’t sit catatonic.
An idea is a mental tool that enables you
to sort and respond to sensory experiences – single ones or whole categories of
them. ("Balsamroot! Tasty.”) (“Poison ivy here. Stay away.") ("That’s
a clip of Dr. King. Real courage.")
When you find an idea that enables quick,
accurate sorting, you keep it. What can confuse and confound this whole picture
is the way that, in the case of many of your most deeply held, deeply
programmed ideas, you didn’t find them. They came by trial-and-error to some of
your ancestors, who found the ideas so useful that they then did their best to
program these ideas into their children. Then, the ideas were passed down the
generations to you.
Many ideas you acquire are added to your
mental toolkit after Bayesian analysis by the process of your own noticing,
considering, and testing them. But you pick up many more ideas from your family
and tribe. This cultural programming is being instilled in you because people
of your tribe acquired, tested, and affirmed those ideas by the first
process. Furthermore, those ideas worked. Your forbears survived well
enough to pass those ideas down the generations to you partly because they had adopted
and used those ideas.
Observe, hypothesize, test, adjust, test
some more: these are the marks of Bayesianism, the model by which we grow,
individually and as nations. And a Bayesian never concludes about any of his ideas that the idea is final or complete.
Culture, consciousness, even sanity, are
constantly evolving for all humans all the time. Each of us keeps updating our
ideas/beliefs. This is true for ideas as complex as justice and love
and as basic as up and down. (Individual minds can
indeed be made to reprogram their notions of up and down.1).
And in this picture, “I” is
a dynamic, self-referencing system that is constantly checking its perceptions
of the evidence in reality against ideas, models, and concepts of what it
believes reality should be, then updating itself.
Admittedly, a few very general ideas are not acquired by humans via either
of the above methods of individual learning or social programming. They are
hardwired into us by our genetic code. They don’t fit into either of the
categories just described. But they fit inside the Empiricist model because
they can be studied by scientists using Empiricist methods.
Some of the genes that cause a language
center to develop in a fetus’ brain are still being identified. The brain areas
holding them also are only partly understood. But they’re being studied in
physical reality (e.g. Broca’s area). They are not Rationalist,
Platonic mysteries.
In our present discussion, we can pass
these innate concepts by. They are biological rather than philosophical –
hardware rather than software – so they are outside of our present scope. These
genes, and the brain structures that are built from the information coded into
them, may even be manipulated one day, for a whole range of possible ends, by
behavior modification, genetic engineering, drugs, surgery, or other
technologies we today can’t imagine.
But for our purposes here, in our search
for a universal code of moral values, Neurophysiology’s usefulness for this
search runs out. Whether techniques for manipulating the brain/mind will be
judged right or wrong and whether they will be allowed in our society will
still depend on values already programmed as “software” into future tribes of
humans. Values like freedom and dignity. These values,
as we have already seen, are going to need something more in the code at their
core than what is offered by our current Science.
Empiricism, as a moral guide, has proved
unreliable in theory and practice. In short, so far, Science has failed at
being its own moral guide.
Even in Neurophysiology, knowing the
structure of the brain cannot tell us how brains should be
used. Brains are hardware; moral codes are software. How we should program
hardware is not revealed by studying hardware. What ideas we should put into
brains is not made clear by studying brains.
Figuring out what we should be programming
into human minds requires that we examine the fit between our software – including, our
moral codes – and reality, i.e. the world. Do our morals work? Do they lead us
to live healthier, wiser lives and, most of all, to survive? In the end,
that is the crucial test of any moral code. This thought returns us to our
project of finding a foundation for some new core software – i.e. finding a new
moral code – and so to Bayesianism.
The Bayesian model of how we think is so
radical that at first it eludes us. To each individual, the idea that he must
continually adjust his entire mindset, and that no parts of it, not even the
most deeply held ideas of who he is or how reality works, can ever be fully
trusted, is disturbing to say the least. Doubting our most basic concepts is like
flirting with mental illness. Even considering the possibility is upsetting.
But this radical Bayesian view is certainly the one I arrive at when I look
back honestly over the changes I have undergone in my own life. The Bayesian
model of how a “self” is formed, and how it evolves as the organism ages, fits
the set of memories that I call my “self” exactly.
Thomas Kuhn is the most famous of the
philosophers who have examined the processes by which people adopt a new
theory, model, or way of knowing. His works focus on how scientists adopt a new
scientific model, but his conclusions can be applied to all thinking. His most
famous book proposes that all our ways of knowing, even our most cherished
ones, are tentative.2 Human knowledge grows and changes, as humans
advance, by paradigm shifts, from obsolete ideas to newer, more effective ones –
i.e. by leaps, rather than in a steady march of gradually growing
understanding. We “get” a new theory by a kind of experience that is like a
religious conversion.
Thus, Kuhn confirms what Bayesianism tells
us about our ways of growing our thinking: real growth is always surprising; it
always moves into newer, better ways of thinking by a revolution inside our
sets of beliefs. The moral code we are aiming to write for future generations
of humans round the world is going to have to take this evolving nature of
human culture into account. Our new code is going to have to provide for its own
constant updating.
Caution and vigilance seem to be the only
rational attitudes to take under such a view of the universe and the human
place in it. To many people, the idea that all the mind’s routines, perhaps
even the mind’s operating system – i.e. its sanity – are tentative and subject
to constant revision seems absurd.
But then again, cognitive dissonance theory leads us to predict that we would dismiss such a scary picture of ourselves. We don’t want to see ourselves as incapable of forming any unshakable beliefs. But History and experience both show that we’re almost completely devoid of any unshakable concepts. (Why I say almost completely will become clear shortly.)
Ultimately, our way of thinking, learning,
and evolving in all matters is either Bayesian or doomed. On the tribal scale, tribes
either evolve or die out. They don’t stay in a steady state of social confluence.
That’s a rule of living. In real existence, there is no other way.
At this point in the discussion, opponents
of Bayesianism begin to marshal their forces. Critics give many reasons for
disagreeing with Bayesianism. I will deal with the two most telling – one is
practical and evidence-based, and the other is theoretical.
We’ll disarm the evidence-based attack in
the next chapter, the theoretical one in the chapter after that.
Notes
1. Jan Degenaar, “Through the Inverting
Glass: First-Person Observations on Spatial Vision and Imagery”
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12,
No. 1 (March 2013).
2. Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of
Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 3rd ed.,
1996).
No comments:
Post a Comment
What are your thoughts now? Comment and I will reply. I promise.